96

Instructions:

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

1. Summary of the reading: People is expected to do the readings so your summary should just aim to remind people of what they have already read instead of detailing the article(s) to an audience that is unfamiliar with the piece. (Key idea, thesis, the goal of this paper, what John Grey argues with Anne Conway)
 

2. Prepare 6 questions that each bring out ideas below for discuss. One idea each. 

1. Main aspects of the reading

2. Problematic aspects of the reading

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

3. Points of comparison with other readings; their relative strengths or weaknesses

4. Strengths of a successful argument

5. Nuances of the answers they provide to the core questions discussed in the course

6. Feminist interpretations of the readings and so on.

1

Forthcoming in Colin Marshall (ed.), Comparative Metaethics: Neglected Perspectives on the

Foundations of Morality, Routledge. Please cite final published version.

Species and the Good in Anne Conway’s Metaethics

John Grey
Michigan State University

1. Introduction

Many Neoplatonist thinkers hold that moral facts are, in the first instance, evaluative
facts about states of being rather than deontic facts about actions. At least for a human,
being wise is good; being “thoroughly mixed with the body” is bad (Enneads I.2, 135); being
rational is better than being irrational; and so on. As these examples indicate, such
evaluations are most easily construed in relation to a particular kind or species. What is a
defect in a human may not be a defect in another sort of being. As Plotinus observes,

“living” means different things in different contexts; it is used in one way of plants,
in another of irrational animals, in various ways by things distinguished from each
other by the clarity or dimness of their life; so obviously the same applies to “living
well.”

(Plotinus, Enneads I.4, 181)

This suggests an account of an important set of evaluative facts, namely those regarding
what states are good or bad (or better or worse) relative to a given species. It is worse for a
human to be blind than to be sighted, but the same does not hold for a deep-sea lobster.
Why? Being sighted is in the nature of human life and not in the nature of deep-sea lobster
life. Moreover, an account along these lines has the advantage of being connected to
ordinary experience. We derive our knowledge of the nature of a species or kind by
observing lots of individual members of that species or kind. Insofar as the facts about what
states are good or bad for an individual follow from what kind of thing it is, our knowledge
of these evaluative facts does not require any special form of perception or intuition.1
It is not all smooth sailing. Neoplatonist authors typically endorse some version of
the “great chain of being,” and on such a picture at least some evaluative facts about states
of being are not merely relative to the kind or species of thing that has that state.2 Being

1 Over and above the basic questions about what these evaluative facts are and how we learn
of them, a contemporary metaethicist might also ask what reason there is to think that such
evaluative facts are prior to other sorts of moral facts, such as facts about how we ought to
act. Authors such as Conway do not directly address this question, as far as I can see, so I
pass over it. For an overview of the metaethical issues involved in the relationship between
the evaluative and the deontic, see Michael Smith 2005, 10-21.
2 A clear example of this sort of picture can be found in, e.g., Book III of Marsilio Ficino’s
Platonic Theology; see Ficino 2001.

2

human is better than being a deep-sea lobster—full stop. Two metaethical difficulties are
posed by such absolute evaluative facts about states of being. Prima facie, such facts cannot
be grounded in the natures of the individuals possessing or lacking those states, since the
individuals could hardly have had a different (better!) nature. Nor can we learn about such
things by observing what is normal or natural for the individual or for its species. On the
face of it, it is entirely normal and natural for a lobster not to be a human. Why then is this
state worse for it than being human would be? What sense can be made of such a claim, and
by what mode of inquiry could we come to learn whether it is true or false?
Here I examine the way that these questions arise for Anne Conway, an early
modern philosopher heavily influenced by Neoplatonism. Her strategy for addressing these
issues is noteworthy because it is derived from a sophisticated theory of essence.3 Conway
recognizes that in order to make sense of species-independent facts about which states of
being are better or worse than others, she must deal with the modal issues that are involved in
making sense of statements such as, “It would be better for this deep-sea lobster to be a
human.” I will argue that Conway rejects essentialism about species membership primarily
because it would entail that “no creature could attain further perfection and greater
participation in the divine goodness” (CC 32) than the limits of their species permitted.4 As a
consequence, the essence of a particular human being does not include her humanity. And
once essentialism about species membership is off the table, there is no problem with taking
species-independent facts about an individual’s good to be grounded in that individual’s
nature after all.
Concerns such as these may seem quite distant from current metaethical interests,
and in many ways they are. Nevertheless, I will conclude by arguing that Conway’s work
bears on a prominent family of contemporary views about an individual’s good that draw on
the notion of an ideally rational, ideally informed version of that individual. As I shall argue,
the construction of such an ideal counterpart typically involves essentialist presuppositions
similar to those that Conway identifies and rejects in her investigations into species and the
good.

2. Background: Conway’s Metaphysics
Since Anne Conway has not (yet) been widely included as part of the canon of early
modern European philosophers, a brief overview of her biography and philosophical system
will be helpful.5

Conway, née Anne Finch, was born in 1631 to Sir Heneage Finch and Elizabeth
Cradock. Heneage Finch was the Recorder of the City of London—a senior judge and high-
level government functionary—as well as Speaker of the House of Commons. We know

3 See Peter Loptson 1982 for extensive discussion of Conway’s peculiar form of essentialism;
I focus in what follows only on those aspects of Conway’s view that pertain to the
metaethical issues raised above.
4 Citations of Allison P. Coudert and Taylor Course’s translation of Conway’s Principles are to
Conway 1996, hereafter ‘CC’. Where the Latin translation of the lost original manuscript is
consulted, citations are also provided to Peter Loptson’s edition, Conway 1982, hereafter ‘L’.
5 For more detailed discussion of Conway’s life and her interactions with other philosophers
and figures of interest, see Loptson 1982 and Sarah Hutton 2004. Useful discussions of
Conway’s shifting intellectual relationship with More over the years may be found in Allison
Coudert 1975 and Jasper Reid 2012, 255-278.

3

little of Conway’s education, but based on the testimony of those familiar with her, she was
fluent in Latin and had at least some knowledge of Greek. Her education took a distinctively
philosophical turn in 1650, when—at the age of nineteen—she began a correspondence with
Henry More. Although Henry More is little studied today, he was the most prolific of the
Cambridge Platonists; indeed, some scholars have made the case that More was the most
influential living philosopher in the latter half of the seventeenth century (read: after
Descartes’s death).6 Under More’s tutelage, Conway studied the works of Plato and Plotinus,
and is thanked in More’s own works as having provided constructive but penetrating
criticism of his arguments. She also learned the intricacies of Cartesian philosophy, though
she did not herself become a Cartesian. Her correspondence with More indicates that she
frequently raised objections to both Morean and Cartesian philosophy. In the earliest
biography of Henry More, the author recalls More describing Conway as “one, that would
not give up her Judgement entirely unto any” (cited in the appendix to L 237). In spite of the
fact that she was often critical of More’s views, the two remained close friends for almost
Conway’s entire life. After her death in 1679, More and another of Conway’s close friends,
Francis Mercury van Helmont, worked to have her philosophical notebook translated into
Latin and published. This was finally accomplished in 1690, when the translated contents of
the notebook were published as the Principles of Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy.

The work is short—the Latin text runs 82 pages with modern typesetting—but
extremely dense. Here I will not canvass the whole of her Principles, though I might note by
way of advertisement that, among other points of interest, she provides a number of striking
objections to both substance dualism and property dualism, and anticipates a version of
Leibniz’s argument against absolute space and time. My focus here will be on the root
structure that feeds into Conway’s metaethics.

Conway’s system presupposes a form of Christian Theism, although her Christianity
is an unorthodox fusion of Platonism, Kabbalism, and early Quakerism.7 Much of her
metaphysics aims at drawing out the consequences of her conception of God and God’s
relationship to creation. On the view she develops, God is a unique, purely spiritual
substance with a number of fairly traditional divine attributes: “God is spirit, light, and life,
infinitely wise, good, just, strong, all-knowing, all-present, all-powerful, the creator and
maker of all things” (CC 9). No attempt is made in the Principles to justify or argue for the
claim that God exists; no attempt is made to show that God is unique; and no attempt is
made to show that God has this particular list of attributes. This conception of God is a
foundational element of Conway’s system. It is important for us because, as the list of God’s
attributes reveals, God has a number of paradigmatically moral properties.

Conway also holds that God is really distinct from, but intimately connected to,
creation:

[God] is also in a true and real sense an essence or substance distinct from his
creatures, although not divided or separate from them but present in everything
most intimately in the highest degree. (CC 9)

6 Reid 2012, 1.
7 On Conway’s Platonism, see Hutton 2018, 242-246; on her kabbalism, see Coudert 1975;
on her Quakerism, see Hutton 2004, ch. 9.

4

Both the real distinction of God from creation and God’s intimate presence in creation are
important foundational elements of her system. The fact that God is really distinct from any
created substance serves to distance Conway from substance monists such as Spinoza, who
“confuse God with his creatures” (CC 31). Yet the intimate presence of the divine in all
creatures is also crucial for Conway’s picture. It leads her to the view that all things must
inherit certain of God’s attributes, at least in some degree.

This point is of particular importance for Conway’s metaethics. She holds that in any
act of creation, there are certain attributes that the created thing can inherit from the creator
(or “communicable” attributes), and others that cannot be so inherited (or
“incommunicable” attributes). Her examples of incommunicable attributes include the
attribute of being a self-subsisting entity or “ens per se subsistens,” being immutable, and being
most perfect (CC 45; L 108). By contrast, “The communicable attributes are that God is
spirit, light, life, that he is good, holy, just, wise” (CC 45), and so on. Notably, although God
has numerous attributes that creatures do not—and cannot—inherit, these are in the first
instance purely metaphysical features of God. The attributes that creatures can and at least to
some degree do inherit from God include his moral properties: being good and being just.
Thus, as Sarah Hutton (2018) has recently argued, there is a sense in which Conway
construes properties such as goodness and justice as specific forms of Godlikeness.8
Perhaps the most distinctive element of Conway’s system, however, is her monistic
view of the created world. She reasons on the basis of the fact that God’s immutability is not
communicable to creatures that there can be at most “three kinds of being [Triplex…Entium
classis]” (CC 24, L 82):

The first is altogether immutable. The second can only change toward the good, so
that which is good by its very nature can become better. The third kind is that which,
although it was good by its very nature, is nevertheless able to change from good to
good as well as from good to evil. (CC 24)

Conway’s inference to this tripartite ontology presupposes, first, that although God has
many attributes, immutability with respect to the good is the attribute that defines the kind of being
he is. She also presupposes that there are only two ways for a being to be changeable or
mutable with respect to the good. Either (i) it has the potential to change only for the better,
or (ii) it has the potential to change both for better and for worse. (The possibility of a being
that can change only for the worse, only becoming less perfect ad infinitum, she rules out as

8 Notably, Hutton holds that, “Conway’s conception of goodness is primarily metaphysical
rather than moral” (230). Her main argument for this claim is that Conway’s account of the
good focuses so much on its ontological or metaphysical side that it is not usefully action-
guiding; it “brings us no nearer to knowing what kind of conduct incurs punishment” (241).
This highlights a genuine difficulty in understanding Conway’s treatment of the good and
somewhat undermines my proposal to examine her as a metaethical thinker. However, I
suspect that this also overstates the problem a bit; given Conway’s lengthy list of God’s
attributes, it seems possible to make reasonable inferences about how an individual ought to
strive to emulate the divine in at least some cases. For example, in virtue of the fact that God
is life, we might expect Conway to see the promotion of life, whether one’s own or
another’s, as good. Acts of violence and self-harm, on such a view, would qualify as sinful
and worthy of punishment.

5

incompatible with the premise that all creatures inherit some degree of God’s goodness.)
Given these presuppositions, however, we arrive at Conway’s tripartite ontology.
She interprets this ontology as describing the following situation. There is a divine
substance, God, which produces “by generation or emanation [generatio vel emanatio]” (CC 25,
L 84) a mediating substance, a being mutable in the sense that it can always become better or
more godlike.9 The divine substance then works through the mediating substance to produce
created substances—including ourselves and other finite individuals—which are mutable in
the sense that they can always become better or worse, more or less godlike.

The most significant consequence of this ontology is that all created individuals are
of the same kind. As many scholars have observed, this is the central part of Conway’s case
against the various forms of mind-body dualism that she considers and rejects in the course
of her Principles.10 The dualism of Descartes fails, for example, because the distinction
between thought and extension does not mark an ontological difference; both spirits and
bodies are created substances, and any further differences among them are mere a matter of
modes or properties, rather than of substance.11 And the fact that a substance bears some
extended modes does not entail that it bears no modes of thought. Thus:

[C]reation is one entity or substance in respect to its nature or essence, as
demonstrated above, so that it only varies according to its modes of existence, one of
which is corporeality. There are many degrees of this so that any thing can approach
or recede more or less from the condition of a body or spirit. Moreover, because
spirit is the more excellent of the two in the true and natural order of things, the
more spiritual a certain body becomes…the closer it comes to God… (CC 42)

Conway is thus an essence monist: she holds that all created individuals have the same nature or
essence.12 She relies upon this point throughout the remainder of the Principles to undermine

9 The mediating substance she usually calls “Christ,” and not merely as a metaphor. She takes
the mediating substance to be the historical Jesus; see CC Chapter 5. However, this fact does
not seem to play much role in the development of her system, which relies more on a priori
argument than appeal to biblical authority.
10 Some valuable discussions of the connection between Conway’s ontology and her
philosophy of mind appear in Jane Duran 1996, Jennifer McRobert 2000, and Julia
Borcherding forthcoming.
11 I develop one of Conway’s versions of this argument at length in John Grey 2017.
12 There are stronger and weaker readings of Conway’s claim that creatures do not differ in
their “substance or essence.” On one reading—endorsed primarily by Hutton 2004 and
Christia Mercer 2012 and 2015—Conway is committing herself to a form of existence
monism about created substance. On another reading, endorsed by Loptson 1982, Duran
1989, Jacqueline Broad 2002, Marcy Lascano 2013, and Grey 2017, Conway merely intends
to claim that creatures are not individuated from one another by their essential features
(since their essence is to be created individual), leaving open the possibility that individual
creatures are individual substances. For an alternative to these two readings, see Jessica
Gordon-Roth 2018. This disagreement may be relevant insofar as Conway’s metaethics is
founded upon her metaphysics of essence; however, I aim to sidestep this issue as much as
possible.

6

a variety of different forms of dualism or materialism.13 Conway wields this monistic
conception of the created world in surprising and powerful ways, and it is without a doubt
one of the most interesting parts of her metaphysics.

Strangely, though, she does not appeal to monism when she makes her case against
essentialism about species membership. There, as I will argue, she relies upon metaethical
considerations instead.

3. The Participation Argument

Conway describes her target as the view that we must assign “specific entities…their
own distinct essences and attributes [specificas rerum Entitates in distinctis suis Essentiis &
Essentialibus attributis]” (CC 32; L 92). She says little more than this to characterize the view
she has in mind, but it is clear from her examples—which range from humans and horses to
ice and stones—that the species in question need not be biological. We might more broadly
understand her concern to be with natural kinds, or sortal properties that carve the created
world into two or more nonempty classes.14 With this caveat in place, the view at issue can
be called

Essentialism about species membership: The essence of a created individual includes

that individual’s species.

Now, one very straightforward reason Conway has for rejecting this view is that, as

we have seen, she is an essence monist: she believes all creatures share the same essence.
Insofar as she allows for the existence of more than one species, she has reason to reject the
claim that the essence of a created thing refers to any species more fine-grained than being a
created thing. The interpretation of Conway’s monism has been the subject of much recent
debate, but all parties to the debate concur on this point.15

I agree that Conway’s ontology gives her reason to reject essentialism about species
membership. Strikingly, though, the passage in which Conway actually does reject that thesis
explicitly appeals only to the fact that it would place limits on creatures’ “participation in
divine goodness” (CC 32), which Conway regards as potentially “infinite” or unlimited. That
is, although Conway has ontological resources to reject essentialism about species
membership, the argument she actually uses is one that provides metaethical reasons for
rejecting that view instead.

13 Notably, Conway also recognizes that some forms of materialism are consonant with the
rejection of species essentialism; see her comparison of her view to Hobbes’ materialism at
CC 65.
14 The interpretation of ‘species’ in this context as referring to natural kinds is shared by
Lascano. Her 2013, 335 n. 10, develops the reading as clearly as I have seen. Loptson
suggests in his Introduction to the Principles that we should understand Conway’s view as the
thesis that there are no natural kinds; see his 1982, 17. However, he takes this to require
Conway to accept a haecceitistic theory of individuation and identity. The rejection of
species essentialism as defined here does not in fact force Conway to accept haecceities, and
I want to be clear that I am not attributing such a view to her. Emily Thomas 2018 develops
a persuasive alternative to Loptson’s haecceitistic interpretation.
15 See note 12 above.

7

To understand these reasons, it will be helpful to examine more closely her
conception of the good. On Conway’s view, strongly influenced by her studies of Plato and
Plotinus, all creatures participate to some extent in divine goodness.16 For all creatures are
created by one and the same divine substance, and as we have seen, Conway takes this to
imply that all creatures inherit that divine substance’s communicable attributes in a limited
degree—including, among other things, goodness and justice. Now, the manner in which
any individual creature participates in these divine attributes at any time during its existence
will be contingent upon its species. For instance, Conway writes that a horse is “a creature
endowed by its creator with different degrees of perfection, such as not only bodily strength
but also certain notions, so to speak, of how to serve his master” (CC 32).17 Presumably a
good human life will involve activities quite different from those involved in a good horse
life. But both forms of life are ways of participating in the good.

Taken on its own, this is not a particularly novel view. It recalls Plotinus’ conclusion
at Enneads I.4, already quoted, that “‘living’…is used in one way of plants, in another of
irrational animals, in various ways by things distinguished from each other by the clarity or
dimness of their life; so obviously the same applies to ‘living well’” (181). However, Conway
holds not only that all creatures participate in divine goodness, but that all creatures have an
unlimited potential to increase their degree of participation in the good. It is this view, I argue,
that motivates her to reject essentialism about species membership.

The explicit rationale that Conway provides for rejecting essentialism about species
membership is, as I noted already, that it places limits on a creature’s potential to participate
in divine goodness. As she sees it, carving up the created world as the species essentialist
does “obscures the glory of the divine attributes so that it cannot shine with its due splendor
in creatures” (ibid.) Her argument runs as follows:

For if a creature were entirely limited by its own individuality and totally constrained
and confined within the very narrow boundaries of its own species to the point that
there was no mediator through which one creature could change into another, then
no creature could attain further perfection and greater participation in divine
goodness [nec ulla ad ulteriorem perfectionem, majoremque divinae bonitatis participationem
evehi], nor could creatures act and react upon each other in different ways. (CC 32)

I take it that in this passage Conway is offering us a modus tollens with an implicit premise:

1. If the essence of a creature includes its species, then its species would place limits
on its potential to “attain further perfection and greater participation in divine
goodness” (CC 32).

2. There are no limits to a creature’s potential to attain further perfection and a
greater degree of participation in divine goodness.

3. So, the essence of a creature does not include its species.

16 In his Preface to the Principles, CC 4, Henry More writes of “her persuing…of both Plato
and Plotinus” in Latin translation.
17 At CC 32, Conway attributes a variety of paradigmatically human mental states and
cognitive abilities to nonhuman animals: “In addition, a horse exhibits anger, fear, love,
memory, and various other qualities which are in human beings.”

8

The thought seems to be that if the species of a creature were essential to it, this would
impose a fixed limit on that creature’s degree of participation in the good. But this would be
in some sense to limit “the glory of the divine attributes” insofar as they are manifest in
creation, or so Conway seems to think. Call this the Participation Argument against essentialism
about species membership.

The justification for the first premise in the Participation Argument is
straightforward enough. Even the best and noblest horse remains stymied by principled
moral reasoning, or for that matter by the use of a doorknob. The form of a horse, the shape
of its body, the structure of its brain: all of these characteristics serve both to define and to
constrain its potential to participate in the good. Thus, if the essence of a particular creature
includes being a horse, inscribed within its very nature are certain limits on the degree to which
that creature can participate in the good.

This thought is clearly connected to the problem I described at the outset. What
Conway has recognized is that if essentialism about species membership is true, there could
be no genuine facts about whether an individual would be better off if it were in a state that
is incompatible with its species.18 A frustrated pet owner, after her dog steals a chocolate bar
from the table, says, “If only I could make you understand that chocolate will hurt your
stomach! It would be so much better for you to be able to talk.” The owner is imagining a
world in which her dog is able to understand her warning about the deleterious effects of
chocolate. Yet the dog’s inability to understand such things is part and parcel of his canine
nature. The species essentialist concludes that the owner is imagining an impossible world.
For the dog to understand his owner’s warning, he would have to be something different
from what he is and must be: a dog.

However, where many today might be inclined to accept the antecedent and infer the
consequent—concluding, among other things, that the highest good of a horse is essentially
different from the highest good of a human—Conway runs the argument in a different
direction. She holds that a creature’s potential for participation in the good must be
unlimited. A fortiori, a creature’s potential must not be limited by constraints imposed by its
species. If the highest good of the horse is not constrained by its horseness, it must be
capable of transcending its species. Or, again, to make sense of the fact that the dog would
really be better off with a degree of understanding that surpasses what any dog is capable of,
we must deny that he is essentially a dog.

That is the logic of Conway’s argument. Still, we might reasonably wonder why a
creature’s potential for goodness is supposed to be unlimited in this way. What justifies this
claim? I can find little in the text to motivate this premise besides a piece of text that
Conway includes in the section immediately following the presentation of the Participation
Argument. There, she writes,

[S]ince the divine power, goodness, and wisdom has created good creatures so that
they may continually and infinitely move towards the good through their own
mutability, the glory of their attributes shines more and more. And this is the nature
of all creatures, namely that they be in continual motion or operation, which most
certainly strives for their further good (just as for the reward and fruit of their own

18 Strictly speaking, all such conditionals would be vacuously true, since their antecedents
would be necessarily false—hence my use of the weaselly “genuine” in describing the
problem.

9

labor), unless they resist that good by a willful transgression and abuse of the
impartial will created in them by God. (CC 32)

The reference here to God’s power, goodness, and wisdom may be shorthand for a further
argument that the possibility of a creature that can attain no further perfection is
incompatible with God’s nature. There is no indication of how this further argument might
go, except that the continual improvement of creatures serves to glorify the divine attributes.
What is clear is Conway’s conclusion: there are in principle no limits to the degree of
goodness or perfection that individual could attain. This is the way that each individual
manifests divine goodness, the way that each individual is godlike.

4. Metaethical Consequences of the Participation Argument

The immediate metaethical consequence of the Participation Argument is
straightforward: it allows us to make sense of facts about the good of a created individual
that are independent of its species. What is good for an individual is not indexed (solely) to
its present species or form. Thus there is no special problem posed by evaluative facts about
whether it would be good or bad for that individual to have a different species or form.
Would I be better off with a dog’s life or not? On Conway’s view, this is a fair question, not
a request for a vacuous frivolity, as an essentialist about species membership would suppose.

One objection that might be raised here, however, is that on this view it is unclear
what the content of an individual creature’s nature consists in, given that it does not include
facts about the species to which that creature belongs. A human isn’t essentially human; but
then what is her essence? This may sound like a purely metaphysical concern about essences,
but it leads directly to a metaethical concern as well. For we might have hoped that
knowledge of a creature’s essence would allow us to make judgments about its good. Most
pressingly, we might have hoped that knowledge of human nature—our own nature—would
lead us to knowledge of what is good for us. Conway’s view seems to imply that this sort of
inference will not work. The fact that I am human is not part of my essence; so it is quite
possible that what is good or bad for me cannot be discerned on the basis of my humanity
alone.

I think this problem is less significant than it seems. The main response is simply
that Conway does allow that a great many facts about what is good or bad for an individual
are determined on the basis of its present species (or form, or kind). An individual’s good is
grounded both in its essence, that of a created individual, and in its present species. For
example, when considering her famous example of a horse, Conway writes:

Now, I ask, to what further perfection or degree of goodness of being or essence
does or can a horse attain after he has performed good services for his master and
has done what was and is appropriate for such a creature? (CC 32, emphasis added)

This quote indicates that the horse’s good includes facts about what is “appropriate” given
its species, even if these do not exhaust its good. There are facts about what is good for a
horse insofar as it is a horse, and also facts about what is good for a horse (what “further
perfection” it can attain) insofar as it is a created individual. A similar implication is present
in one of Conway’s few first-order moral discussions:

10

[A] man who has a tree in his orchard that is fruitful and grows well fertilizes and
prunes it so that it becomes better and better. But if it is barren and a burden to the
earth, he fells it with an ax and burns it. (CC 35)

This is an odd passage, but I suggest we read it as a reflection of both facets of Conway’s
conception of the good. On the one hand, there are facts about what is good for the tree
insofar as it is a tree—that it is good for the tree to be fruitful and fertilized, for example. On
the other hand, there are facts about what is good for the tree insofar as it is a created
individual—in this case, that it be cut down and thereby transformed when it can no longer
reach further excellence as a tree. In light of this distinction, then, Conway can grant that
many of the facts about our good are indeed grounded in our humanity.
There is another metaethical consequence of this argument—or at least Conway
takes it to be a consequence of the argument—that is perhaps harder to swallow. On
Conway’s view, the rejection of essentialism about species membership leads to a view we
might call the universality of moral subjecthood, according to which all creatures are moral
subjects. That Conway accepts the universality of moral subjecthood is clear from her
discussion of “the justice of God”:

We already see how the justice of God shines so gloriously in this transmutation of
one species into another. … When they become better, this justice bestows a reward
and prize for their good deeds. When they become worse, the same justice punishes
them with fitting penalties according to the nature and degree of their transgression.
The same justice imposes a law for all creatures and inscribes it in their very natures.
Whatever creature breaks this law is punished accordingly. But any creature who
observes this law receives the reward of becoming better. (CC 35)

The moral law that humans must abide by is not unique to humanity, but inscribed in the
nature of all creatures—and all creatures are rightly subject to reward or punishment
according to their behavior.

Why accept such a view? Notably, this passage comes shortly after Conway’s
discussion of the Participation Argument; it seems to be a continuation of her thinking
about the consequences of the view that all creatures can “attain further perfection and
greater participation in divine goodness” (CC 32). The connection may seem oblique, but I
think Conway has in mind something like the following line of reasoning. Once we open up
questions about what a creature would be like if it were a spiritually and morally improved
version of itself—treating such counterfactuals as genuine metaphysical possibilities—there
is no reason to treat humans alone as subject to morality. For humans are responsible for
failing to act in accordance with the divine law because (i) they have access to the law (it is
inscribed in their nature) and (ii) they could have acted in accordance with it. Given that the
nature or essence of a human does not include her humanity, however, it cannot be her
humanity that gives her access to the divine law. As the passage just quoted indicates, the
divine law is imposed upon us not in virtue of our humanity, but simply in virtue of our
nature as created beings. Moreover, on Conway’s view, the species of an individual does not
determine what it could or could not do. Thus, even when an individual actually lacks
psychological features we might take to be prerequisites for morality, nevertheless that

11

individual could have had those features.19 So it is true not only of humans, but of all
creatures, that they could have both (i) recognized and (ii) acted in accordance with the
divine law. While this interpretation involves some rational reconstruction, it would explain
Conway’s readiness to consider all creatures as moral subjects, taking actions for which they
may rightly be rewarded or punished.

5. Lessons for Metaethics
Conway’s willingness to endorse the universality of moral subjecthood, if nothing
else, should highlight for us the distance between her metaethical views and those in vogue
today. This may make it seem as though the study of her system has little to offer the
contemporary metaethicist. However, I will conclude by outlining one way in which
Conway’s system draws our attention to some hidden assumptions about essentialism that
are at work in an influential family of contemporary metaethical views about the good.

A number of authors over the past forty years or so have developed versions of the
view that a person’s normative reasons—loosely, the practical or moral reasons that count
for or against that person’s acting in certain ways—are (or are determined by) facts about an
idealized version of that person. (I’ll use ‘reason’ as shorthand for “normative reason” from
here on.) This literature is likely more familiar than the scholarly conversation on Anne
Conway, so a few key examples should suffice to illustrate the general strategy. Peter Railton
(1986, 16) writes,

[A]n individual’s good consists in what he would want himself to want, or to pursue,
were he to contemplate his present situation from a standpoint fully and vividly
informed about himself and his circumstances, and entirely free of cognitive error or
lapses of instrumental rationality.

On the assumption that a person has a reason to do what it is good for him to do, this
suggests that we have a reason to do what this ideal version of ourselves would want to want
in our situation. In a similar vein, Michael Smith (1994, 151) proposes that

[W]hat it is desirable for us to do in certain circumstances—let’s call these
circumstances the ‘evaluated possible world’—is what we, not actually as we are, but
as we would be in a possible world in which we are fully rational—let’s call this the
‘evaluating possible world’—would want ourselves to do in those circumstances.

19 One objection here is that Conway’s view renders useless the principle that ought implies
can. For it seems that there are almost no moral demands that a creature could not have
satisfied, on Conway’s extremely permissive notion of what a creature can do or become.
Thus creatures seem destined not only to be moral subjects, but to be terrible moral subjects.
There are two points to make in reply to this apt concern. First, the idea of the created world
as fallen and corrupt would be in keeping with Neoplatonism. I do not think she would find
this implication of her view to be objectionable, even if we find it uncomfortable. And,
second, I would suggest that we see Conway’s view as adding a further condition for using
ought-implies-can. To use that claim in an appropriately rigorous way, we would first need a
principled account of what an individual can do or become. Thanks to Joseph Len Miller
and Kevin DeLapp for discussion of this issue.

12

Thus, Smith continues, “facts about what it is desirable for us to do are constituted by the
facts about what we would advise ourselves to do if we were perfectly placed to give
ourselves advice” (152). Again, given the assumption that we have a normative reason to do
whatever it is desirable for us to do, this suggests that we have a normative reason to do
what we would be advised to do by an idealized version of ourselves.

Without worrying too much about the differences among such views—which are
important when weighing them against one another, but are not so important for my
purposes here—we can characterize the strategy in Smith’s terms. Call it the

Ideal adviser strategy: x has a normative reason to A iff a perfectly rational
counterpart of x would advise x to A.

The ideal adviser strategy has a number of benefits, not least of which is that it is a naturalistic
way of generating normative reasons. It also makes easy sense of many ordinary cases. (We
do not typically even need to resort to a strictly ideal version of ourselves, either. Although
that neck tattoo really seemed desirable when I was drunk, in the sober light of day I see that it
is not really so…)
There is a significant literature raising difficulties for such accounts.20 My aim here is
more modest: I want to show that those who pursue the ideal adviser strategy must either
accept essentialism about species membership or the universality of moral subjecthood. I
will focus on biological species in developing this point, but recall that ‘species’ here could
include all natural kinds—not only such biological kinds as being human, but also such kinds
as being rational.21 The dilemma may therefore be reframed as follows: if the ideal adviser
theorist wishes to reject the universality of moral subjecthood, he must hold that an
individual’s essence includes some natural kind (humanity, rationality, or whatever) that
moral non-subjects lack.
Although Conway’s metaethics is steeped in religious concerns and motivations that
may seem distant from the ideal adviser strategy, notice that her basic insight is at its core a
version of that strategy. Our good is determined at least in part by facts about more perfect
versions of ourselves—the better creatures we may yet become. And, given that essentialism
about species membership is false, the more perfect version of ourselves need not share our
current traits (e.g., the irrationality of the drunk), or even be human at all. It is this basic line
of thinking that leads Conway to accept the universality of moral subjecthood.
The connection Conway draws between the metaphysics of essence and the
metaethics of moral agency therefore raises the question of whether a similar dynamic may
be at work in the ideal adviser strategy. It seems that it is. If we deny essentialism about any
species membership, it seems that it would be arbitrary to deny that nonhuman creatures
such as dogs or horses have ideally informed counterparts. Given the ideal adviser strategy,
we would then be forced to say of these nonhumans that they have normative reasons to do,
or not to do, certain things, even if they would not normally be reckoned as agents at all.

20 David Sobel 1994, 793, nicely captures the central difficulty for the ideal adviser strategy:
“The idealization process turns us into such different creatures that it would be surprising if
the well-being of the two of us, my informed self and my ordinary self, consisted in the same
things.” The difficulty is figuring out just what criteria one ought to seek in an ideal adviser.
21 Thanks to Colin Marshall for raising this point.

13

Conway, as we have seen, endorses this conclusion. I expect most contemporary
metaethicists will be eager to choose differently, accepting essentialism about species
membership and thereby shutting the door on Conway’s menagerie of dubious moral
subjects. This is an open and perfectly legitimate response. But I do not think there are other
ways out that are not objectionably arbitrary.22 For example, you might be tempted to
propose a restriction on the domain of individuals considered in the ideal adviser strategy, a
restriction that does not rely on essentialism about species membership. Following Connie S.
Rosati (1995, 301), for instance, we might require not only that the idealized version of x
would recommend something, but also that x herself is “capable of caring under ordinary
optimal conditions about the fact that she would care about [something] for her actual self
under a specified set of ideal conditions.” In other words, it is not enough that the ideal
adviser would make a certain recommendation. You must also be able to care about that
recommendation—and Conway’s menagerie cannot do that. In this way, we might try to
restrict moral subjecthood to humans (and perhaps a few other very similar creatures)
without accepting essentialism about species membership.
Yet without essentialism about species membership to back it up, this proposal is
arbitrary. Whether x could care about the advice of her ideal counterpart “under ordinary
optimal conditions” depends on what such conditions are, and it seems that what “ordinary”
and “optimal” here must mean is ordinary and optimal for a member of this species. The idea is
to exclude dogs, for example, as moral agents because it isn’t possible for a dog to care about
what his ideal adviser would recommend, even under ordinary and optimal conditions for a
dog. But then—given that essentialism about species membership is not supposed to be on
the table—it is hard to see what justification there could be for tacking this requirement onto
the ideal adviser strategy.23

One lesson of Conway’s reflections on the good, then, is that our views about the
good may involve us in a great deal more metaphysical presupposition about our capacities
and limits than we typically appreciate. While it is always open to us simply to accept these
presuppositions when they are pointed out to us, they nevertheless represent a cost of such
views that is often left hidden.

22 I suspect that any attempt to fix the problem by restricting the modal accessibility relation
at issue in the ideal adviser strategy will introduce some degree of arbitrariness. For instance,
we might naturally want to restrict the domain of counterparts to those, roughly speaking,
accessible from here and now—that is, those at suitably close possible worlds. Under this
restriction, most nonhumans will lack relevantly informed and rational counterparts, so the
dilemma appears to vanish. However, the restriction requires us to decide what counts as
accessible from here and now, and it seems inevitable that this decision will be somewhat
arbitrary. What counterparts are too distant to make the cut, and why? It is hard to see how a
principled line could be drawn. Thanks to Alex King for pressing me to think more carefully
about this approach.
23 A similar concern afflicts other, even more carefully targeted versions of this approach.
Suppose we modify the ideal adviser strategy as follows: x has a normative reason to A iff a
perfectly rational counterpart of x—who is of the same species as x—would advise x to A. The
problem is that there is no reason to add the extra clause unless we take x’s species to
characterize the ideal version of x, a claim that seems once again to be drawn from
essentialism about species membership.

14

References
Conway, Anne. 1982. Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy. Translated and edited

by Peter Loptson. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Conway, Anne. 1996. The Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy. Translated and

edited by Allison P. Coudert and Taylor Corse. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.

Coudert, Allison. “A Cambridge Platonist’s Kabbalist Nightmare.” Journal of the History of
Ideas 36 no. 4: 633-652.

Borcherding, Julia. Forthcoming. “Loving the Body, Loving the Soul: Conway’s Vitalist
Critique of Cartesian and Morean Dualism.” Oxford Studies in the History of Early
Modern Philosophy, volume 9.

Broad, Jacqueline. 2002. Women Philosophers of the Seventeenth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.

Duran, Jane. 1989. “Anne Viscountess Conway: A Seventeenth Century Rationalist.” Hypatia
4(1): 64-79.

Ficino, Marsilio. 2001. Platonic Theology, Vol. I. Translated by Michael J. B. Allen and John
Warden. Edited by James Hankins and William Bowen. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.

Gordon-Roth, Jessica. Forthcoming. “What Kind of Monist is Anne Finch Conway?” Journal
of the American Philosophical Association.

Grey, John. 2017. “Conway’s Ontological Objection to Cartesian Dualism.” Philosophers’
Imprint 17(3): 1-19.

Hutton, Sarah. 2004. Anne Conway: A Woman Philosopher. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.

Hutton, Sarah. 2018. “Goodness in Anne Conway’s Metaphysics.” In Early Modern Women on
Metaphysics, edited by Emily Thomas, 229-246. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.

Lascano, Marcy. 2013. “Anne Conway: Bodies in the Spiritual World.” Philosophy Compass
8(4): 327-336.

Loptson, Peter. 1982. Introduction to The Principles of the Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy,
by Anne Conway. Boston: Martinus Nijhoff.

McRobert, Jennifer. 2000. “Anne Conway’s Vitalism and Her Critique of Descartes.”
International Philosophical Quarterly XL 1(157): 21-35.

Mercer, Christia. 2012. “Knowledge and Suffering in Early Modern Philosophy: G. W.
Leibniz and Anne Conway.” In Emotional Minds, edited by Sabrina Ebbersmeyer,
179-206. Berlin: De Gruyter.

Mercer, Christia. 2015. “Seventeenth-Century Universal Sympathy: Stoicism, Platonism,
Leibniz, and Conway.” In Sympathy: A History, edited by Eric Schliesser. New York:
Oxford University Press.

Railton, Peter. 1986. “Facts and Values.” Philosophical Topics 14: 5-29.
Reid, Jasper. 2012. The Metaphysics of Henry More. London: Springer.
Rosati, Connie S. 1995. “Persons, Perspectives, and Full Information Accounts of the

Good.” Ethics 105 no. 2: 296-325.
Smith, Michael. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell.
Smith, Michael. 2005. “Meta-ethics.” In Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy, edited by

Frank Jackson and Michael Smith, 3-30. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sobel, David. 1994. “Full Information Accounts of Well-Being.” Ethics 104 no. 4: 784-810.

15

Thomas, Emily. 2018. “Anne Conway on the Identity of Creatures over Time.” In Early
Modern Women on Metaphysics, edited by Emily Thomas, 131-149. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.

Calculate your order
Pages (275 words)
Standard price: $0.00
Client Reviews
4.9
Sitejabber
4.6
Trustpilot
4.8
Our Guarantees
100% Confidentiality
Information about customers is confidential and never disclosed to third parties.
Original Writing
We complete all papers from scratch. You can get a plagiarism report.
Timely Delivery
No missed deadlines – 97% of assignments are completed in time.
Money Back
If you're confident that a writer didn't follow your order details, ask for a refund.

Calculate the price of your order

You will get a personal manager and a discount.
We'll send you the first draft for approval by at
Total price:
$0.00
Power up Your Academic Success with the
Team of Professionals. We’ve Got Your Back.
Power up Your Study Success with Experts We’ve Got Your Back.

Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code ESSAYHELP