Philosophy Paper 2

 

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

There are 6 (specific) requirements which must be fulfilled. However, you are ultimately responsible for choosing the topic and direction of your essay. There are obviously general requirements of any argumentative paper but I will add a rubric outline for argumentative papers below.

If you muck up one of these, then expects big points off of your paper:

1. Find a movie, short story, documentary, or complex news item (not a one-page article but only investigative or in-depth pieces, check with me if you are unsure) to base your analysis around and focus your thesis.

I have given you a few suggestions: the movie “Her” for philo of mind or personal identity and “Minority Report” for free will.

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

2. You must present a philosophy of mind, personal identity, philosophy of religion, or free will topic. The purpose is to argue/explain, for example, a theory in the philosophy of mind or personal identity in terms of the movie “Her”. Examples: Functionalism, Substance Dualism, Memory Theory, etc… In this case, you would be arguing that the character Sam is a mind or how to interpret Sam as a person over time as a way to make the case that the theory you are advancing/argueing for is the best answer to the mind-body problem.

3. Include an objection to your view. Some possibilities:

Could there be another theory that best explains our intuitions about thought experiments in the movie/show?

Does your theory lead to some absurd consequences whether in real life or via the movie’s world?

Is there a possible way to develop a contrasting view of the OSes from the behavior of one of the characters?

4. Include discussions of the thought experiments, ideas, philosophers found in the textbook and links given to you by the prof.

5. You must include one secondary source and provide a full works-cited page. (This means citing the articles we used IN CLASS, from the research, the textbook, and EC work). This also means you SHOULD be using the course material to help make your case in addition to the secondary source from the textbook.

6. Word Minimum: Roughly 1500 -1800 words (MINIMUM). It is permissible to go over the 1800 words if needed (no excuses about not knowing you could write more to fulfill the tasks).

1

Existentialism is a Humanism

Jean-Paul Sartre, 1945

1

My purpose here is to defend existentialism against several reproaches that have been laid
against it.

Existentialism has been criticised for inviting people to remain in a quietism of despair, to fall
back into a the middle-class luxury of a merely contemplative philosophy. We are reproached
for underlining human nastiness, and forgetting, as the Catholic Mme. Mercier has it, the smile
of the child. All and sundry reproach us for treating men as isolated beings, largely because we
begin with the ‘I think’ of Descartes. Christians especially reproach us for denying the reality
and seriousness of human society, since, if we ignore God’s eternal values, no-one is able to
condemn anyone else.

Existentialism is being seen as ugliness; our appeal to nature as scandalous, our writings
sickening. Yet what could be more disillusioning than repeating those mottoes like ‘don’t fight
against tradition’, or ‘know your station’? They say that man is base and doomed to fall, he
needs fixed rules to keep him from anarchy. In the end, is not what makes our doctrine so
fearful to some merely the fact that it leaves all possibility of choice with man?

It has become fashionable to call this painter, or musician or columnist an “existentialist” – a
term so loosely applied that it no longer means anything at all.

However, it can be defined easily. Existentialists are either Christian, such as the Catholics
Jaspers and Gabriel Marcel, or atheists like Heidegger and myself. What they have in common is
to believe that existence comes before essence, that we always begin from the subjective.

What does this mean? If one considers a manufactured object, say a book or a paper-knife, one
sees that it has been made to serve a definite purpose. It has an essence, the sum of its purpose
and qualities, which precedes its existence. The concept of man in the mind of God is
comparable to the concept of paper-knife in the mind of the artisan.

My atheist existentialism is rather more coherent. It declares that God does not exist, yet there
is still a being in whom existence precedes essence, a being which exists before being defined
by any concept, and this being is man or, as Heidegger puts it, human reality.

That means that man first exists, encounters himself and emerges in the world, to be defined

1
Squashed version edited by Glyn Hughes: http://www.btinternet.com/~glynhughes/squashed/sartre.htm

2

afterwards. Thus, there is no human nature, since there is no God to conceive it. It is man who
conceives himself, who propels himself towards existence. Man becomes nothing other than
what is actually done, not what he will want to be.

And when we say that man takes responsibility for himself, we say more than that – he is in his
choices responsible for all men. All our acts of creating ourselves create at the same time an
image of man such as we believe he must be. Thus, our personal responsibility is vast, because
it engages all humanity.

If I want, say, to marry and have children, such choice may depend on my situation, my passion,
my desire, but by it I engage not only myself, but all humanity in the way of the monogamy. In
fashioning myself, I fashion man. This helps us to understand some rather grandiloquent words
like anguish, abandonment, despair.

The existentialist declares that man is in anguish, meaning that he who chooses cannot escape
a deep responsibility for all humanity. Admittedly, few people appear to be anxious; but we
claim that they mask their anguish, that they flee it.

This is what Kierkegaard called the anguish of Abraham. You know the old story: An angel
commanded Abraham to sacrifice his son. But anyone in such a case would wonder straight
away, is this an angel? am I the Abraham? If we hear voices from the sky, what proves that they
come not from hell, or the subconscious, or some pathological state? Who proves that they are
addressed to me?

Each man must say to himself: am I right to set the standard for all humanity? To deny that is to
mask the anguish. When, for example, a military leader sends men to their deaths, he may have
his orders, but at the bottom it is he alone who chooses.

And when we speak about ‘abandonment’, we want to say that God does not exist, and that it
is necessary to follow this conclusion to its end.

The existentialist is strongly against that sloppy morality which tries to remove God without
ethical expense, like the French professors of the 1880’s who saw God as a useless and
expensive assumption but still wanted definitive rules like ‘do not lie’ to exist a priori.

The existentialist, on the contrary, finds it rather embarrassing that God does not exist, for
there disappears with him any possibility of finding values in a heaven. Dostoevsky wrote “If
God did not exist, everything would be permitted”; that is the starting point of existentialism.

We are alone, without excuses. That is what I mean when I say that man is condemned to be
free. There is no power of ‘beautiful passions’ which propel men to their actions, we think,
rather, that man is responsible for his own passions.

The existentialist cannot accept that man can be helped by any sign on earth, for he will

3

interpret the sign as he chooses. As Ponge has truly written “Man is the future of man”.

To give you an example of this ‘abandonment’, I will quote the case of one of my pupils who
came to me. He lived alone with his mother, his father having gone off as a collaborator and his
brother killed in 1940. He had a choice – to go and fight with the Free French to avenge his
brother and protect his nation, or to stay and be his mother’s only consolation. So he was
confronted by two modes of action; one concrete and immediate but directed only towards
one single individual; the other addressed to an infinitely greater end but very ambiguous.
What would help him choose? Christian doctrine? Accepted morals? Kant?

I said to him, “In the end, it is your feelings which count”. But how can we put a value on a
feeling?

At least, you may say, he sought the counsel of a professor. But, if you seek advice, from a
priest for example, in choosing which priest you know already, more or less, what they would
advise.

When I was imprisoned, I met a rather remarkable man, a Jesuit who had joined that order in
the following way: As a child, his father had died leaving him in poverty. At school he was made
to feel that he was accepted only for charity’s sake and denied the usual pleasures. At eighteen
he came to grief in a sentimental affair and then failed his military examinations. He could
regard himself as a total failure, but, cleverly, took it as a sign that the religious life was the way
for him. He saw the word of God there, but who can doubt that the decision was his and his
alone? He could as easily have chosen to be a carpenter or a revolutionary.

As for ‘despair’, this simply means that we will restrict ourselves to relying only on our own will,
or on the probabilities which make our action possible. If I am counting on the arrival of a
friend, I presuppose that their train will be on time. But I am still among possibilities, outside
my own field of action. No God, no intention, is going to alter the world to my will.

In the end, Descartes meant the same, that we must act without hope.

Marxists have answered “Your action is limited by your death, but you can rely on others to
later take up your deeds and carry them forward to the revolution”. To this I rejoin that I cannot
know where the revolution will lead. Others may come and establish Fascism. Does that mean
that I must give up myself to quietism? No!

Quietism is the attitude of people who say: “let others do what I cannot do”. The doctrine that I
present is precisely the opposite: there is reality only in the action; and more, man is nothing
other than his own project and exists only in as far as he carries it out.

From this we see why our ideas so often cause horror. Many people have but one resource to
sustain them in their misery; to think, “circumstances were against me, I was worthy of better. I
had no great love because I never met anyone worthy of me. I wrote no great book because I

4

had no time. I am filled with a crowd of possibilities greater than anyone could guess from my
few achievements.”

But in reality, for the existentialist, there is no love other than that which is built, no artistic
genius other than in works of art. The genius of Proust is the works of Proust. A man engages in
his own life, draws his own portrait, there is nothing more.

This is hard for somebody who has not made a success of life. But it is only reality that counts,
not dreams, expectations or hopes. What people reproach us for here is not our pessimism, but
the sternness of our optimism.

If people reproach our writings, it is not because we describe humanity as frail and sometimes
frankly bad, but because, unlike Zola whose characters are shown to be products of heredity or
environment, you cannot say of ours “That is what we are like, no one can do anything about
it”. The existentialist portrays a coward as one who makes himself a coward by his actions, a
hero who makes himself heroic.

Some still reproach us for confining man within his individual subjectivity. But there is no other
starting-point than the “I think, I am” – the absolute truth of consciousness, a simple truth
within reach of everyone and the only theory which gives man the dignity of not being a mere
object.

All materialisms treat men as objects, no different in their being bundles of determined
reactions than a table or a chair or a stone. We want to constitute a human kingdom of values
distinct from the material world.

Contrary to the philosophy of Descartes, contrary to the philosophy of Kant, we are discovering
in the cogito not just ourselves but all others. We discover an intersubjective world where each
man has to decide what he is and what others are.

It is not possible to find in each man the universal essence called human nature, but there is a
human universality of condition. Any purpose, even that of the Chinese, or the idiot or the child
can be understood by a European, given enough information. In this sense, there is a
universality of man; but it is not a given, it is something perpetually re-built.

That does not entirely refute the charge of subjectivism. People tax us with anarchy; they say
that “you cannot judge others, because you have no reason to prefer one project to another.
You give with one hand what you pretend to receive from the other.”

Let us say that moral choice is comparable to a work of art. Do we reproach the artist who
makes a painting without starting from laid-down rules? Did we tell him what he must paint?
There is no pre-defined picture, and no-none can say what the painting of tomorrow should be;
one can judge only one at a time.

5

Amongst morals, the creative situation is the same, and just as the works of, say, Picasso, have
consequences, so do our moral judgements.

That student who came to me could not appeal to any system for guidance; he was obliged to
invent the law for himself. We define man only through his engagement, so it is absurd to
reproach us for the consequences of a choice.

But it is not entirely true that we cannot judge others. We can judge whether choices are
founded on truth or error, and we can judge a man’s sincerity.

The man who hides behind the excuse of his passions or of some deterministic doctrine, is a
self-deceiver. “And what if I wish to deceive myself?” – there is no reason why you should not,
but I declare publicly that you are doing so.

We will freedom for the sake of freedom. And through it we discover that our freedom depends
entirely on the freedom of others, and that their freedom depends on ours. Those who hide
their freedom behind deterministic excuses, I will call cowards. Those who pretend that their
own existence was necessary, I will call scum.

To the objection that “You receive with one hand what you give with the other”, that is, your
values are not serious, since you choose them, I answer that, I am sorry, but having removed
God the Father, one needs somebody to invent values. Things have to be taken as they are.

One has reproached me ridiculing a type of humanism in Nausea, and now suggesting that
existentialism is a form of humanism. The absurd type of humanism is to glory in “Man the
magnificent” ascribing to all men the value of the deeds of the most distinguished men. Only a
dog or a horse would be in a position to declare such a judgement.

We cannot, either, fall into worshipping humanity, for that way leads to Fascism.

But there is another humanism, the acceptance that there is only one universe, the universe of
human subjectivity. Existentialism is not despair. It declares rather that even if God did exist, it
would make no difference.

“What Makes a Life
Significant?” by William

James

William James, Thoemmes Press

About the author. . . . William James (

1

842-1910), perhaps the most promi-
nent American philosopher and psychologist, was an influential formula-
tor and spokesperson for pragmatism. Early in his life, James studied art,
but later his curiosity turned to a number of scientific fields. After gradua-
tion from Harvard Medical College, James’ intellectual pursuits broadened
to include literary criticism, history, and philosophy. He read widely and
contributed to many different academic fields. The year following gradu-
ation, James accompanied Louis Agassiz on an expedition to Brazil.1 As
a Harvard professor in philosophy and psychology, James achieved recog-
nition as one of the most outstanding writers and lecturers of his time.

About the work. . . . In his Talks to Students,2 James presents three lectures
to students—two of them, being “The Gospel of Relaxation,” and “On a
Certain Blindness in Human Beings.” The third talk is the one presented
here. His second, “On a Certain Blindness in Human Beings,” has as its

1. See the short essay, “In the Laboratory With Agassiz,” by Samuel H. Scudder, in
Chapter 1.
2. William James.Talks to Students. 1899.

1

“What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

thesis that the worth of things depends upon the feelings we have toward
them. Read it online as a companion piece to this reading at theWilliam
JamesWebsite noted below in the section entitled “

  • Related Ideas
  • .”

    From the reading. . .

    “Every Jack sees in his own particular Jill charms and perfections
    to the enchantment of which we stolid onlookers are stone-cold.”

    The Selection from “What Makes Life
    a Significant?”

    [Life’s Values and Meanings]
    IN my previous talk, “On a Certain Blindness,” I tried to make you feel
    how soaked and shot-through life is with values and meanings which we
    fail to realize because of our external and insensible point of view. The
    meanings are there for the others, but they are not there for us. There lies
    more than a mere interest of curious speculation in understanding this. It
    has the most tremendous practical importance. I wish that I could convince
    you of it as I feel it myself. It is the basis of all our tolerance, social, reli-
    gious, and political. The forgetting of it lies at the root of every stupid and
    sanguinary mistake that rulers over subject-peoples make. The first thing
    to learn in intercourse with others is non-interference with their own pecu-
    liar ways of being happy, provided those ways do not assume to interfere
    by violence with ours. No one has insight into all the ideals. No one should
    presume to judge them off-hand. The pretension to dogmatize about them
    in each other is the root of most human injustices and cruelties, and the
    trait in human character most likely to make the angels weep.

    Every Jack sees in his own particular Jill charms and perfections to the
    enchantment of which we stolid onlookers are stone-cold. And which has
    the superior view of the absolute truth, he or we? Which has the more vital
    insight into the nature of Jill’s existence, as a fact? Is he in excess, being in

    2 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    this matter a maniac? or are we in defect, being victims of a pathological
    anæsthesia as regards Jill’s magical importance? Surely the latter; surely to
    Jack are the profounder truths revealed; surely poor Jill’s palpitating little
    life-throbsare among the wonders of creation,are worthy of this sympa-
    thetic interest; and it is to our shame that the rest of us cannot feel like
    Jack. For Jack realizes Jill concretely, and we do not. He struggles toward
    a union with her inner life, divining her feelings, anticipating her desires,
    understanding her limits as manfully as he can, and yet inadequately, too;
    for he is also afflicted with some blindness, even here. Whilst we, dead
    clods that we are, do not even seek after these things, but are contented
    that that portion of eternal fact named Jill should be for us as if it were
    not. Jill, who knows her inner life, knows that Jack’s way of taking it—so
    importantly—is the true and serious way; and she responds to the truth
    in him by taking him truly and seriously, too. May the ancient blindness
    never wrap its clouds about either of them again! Where would any ofus
    be, were there no one willing to know us as we really are or ready to repay
    us for our insight by making recognizant return? We ought, all of us, to
    realize each other in this intense, pathetic, and important way.

    If you say that this is absurd, and that we cannot be in love with everyone
    at once, I merely point out to you that, as a matter of fact, certain persons
    do exist with an enormous capacity for friendship and for taking delight
    in other people’s lives; and that such persons know more of truth than if
    their hearts were not so big. The vice of ordinary Jack and Jill affection is
    not its intensity, but its exclusions and its jealousies. Leave those out, and
    you see that the ideal I am holding up before you, however impracticable
    to-day, yet contains nothing intrinsically absurd.

    We have unquestionably a great cloud-bank of ancestral blindness weigh-
    ing down upon us, only transiently riven here and there by fitful revela-
    tions of the truth. It is vain to hope for this state of things to alter much.
    Our inner secrets must remain for the most part impenetrable by others, for
    beings as essentially practical as we are necessarily short of sight. But, if
    we cannot gain much positive insight into one another, cannot we at least
    use our sense of our own blindness to make us more cautious in going
    over the dark places? Cannot we escape some of those hideous ancestral
    intolerances; and cruelties, and positive reversals of the truth?

    For the remainder of this hour I invite you to seek with me some principle
    to make our tolerance less chaotic. And, as I began my previous lecture by
    a personal reminiscence, I am going to ask your indulgence for a similar
    bit of egotism now.

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 3

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James
    From the reading. . .

    “. . . I merely point out to you that, as a matter of fact, certain persons
    do exist with an enormous capacity for friendship and for taking
    delight in other people’s lives; and that such persons know more of
    truth than if their hearts were not so big. ”

    A few summers ago I spent a happy week at the famous Assembly Grounds
    on the borders of Chautauqua Lake. The moment one treads that sacred
    enclosure, one feels one’s self in an atmosphere of success. Sobriety and
    industry, intelligence and goodness, orderliness and ideality, prosperity
    and cheerfulness, pervade the air. It is a serious and studious picnic on
    a gigantic scale. Here you have a town of many thousands of inhabitants,
    beautifully laid out in the forest and drained, and equipped with means
    for satisfying all the necessary lower and most of the superfluous higher
    wants of man. You have a first-class college in full blast. You have mag-
    nificent music—a chorus of seven hundred voices, with possibly the most
    perfect open-air auditorium in the world. You have every sort of athletic
    exercise from sailing, rowing, swimming, bicycling, to the ball-field and
    the more artificial doings which the gymnasium affords. You have kinder-
    gartens and model secondary schools. You have general religious services
    and special club-houses for the several sects. You have perpetually running
    soda-water fountains, and daily popular lectures by distinguished men.
    You have the best of company, and yet no effort. You have no zymotic dis-
    eases, no poverty, no drunkenness, no crime, no police. You have culture,
    you have kindness, you have cheapness, you have equality, you have the
    best fruits of what mankind has fought and bled and striven for under the
    name of civilization for centuries. You have, in short, a foretaste of what
    human society might be, were it all in the light, with no suffering and no
    dark corners.

    I went in curiosity for a day. I stayed for a week, held spell-bound by the
    charm and ease of everything, by the middle-class paradise, without a sin,
    without a victim, without a blot, without a tear.

    And yet what was my own astonishment, on emerging into the dark and
    wicked world again, to catch myself quite unexpectedly and involuntarily
    saying: “Ouf! what a relief! Now for something primordial and savage,
    even though it were as bad as an Armenian massacre, to set the balance
    straight again. This order is too tame, this culture too second-rate, this

    4 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    goodness too uninspiring. This human drama without a villain or a pang;
    this community so refined that ice-cream soda-water is the utmost offer-
    ing it can make to the brute animal in man; this city simmering in the tepid
    lakeside sun; this atrocious harmlessness of all things,—I cannot abide
    with them. Let me take my chances again in the big outside worldly wilder-
    ness with all its sins and sufferings. There are the heights and depths, the
    precipices and the steep ideals, the gleams of the awful and the infinite;
    and there is more hope and help a thousand times than in this dead level
    and quintessence of every mediocrity.”

    The Boat Landing, Lake Chautauqua, New York, Library of Congress

    Such was the sudden right-about-face performed for me by my lawless
    fancy! There had been spread before me the realization—on a small, sam-
    ple scale of course—of all the ideals for which our civilization has been
    striving: security, intelligence, humanity, and order; and here was the in-
    stinctive hostile reaction, not of the natural man, but of a so-called culti-
    vated man upon such a Utopia. There seemed thus to be a self-contradiction
    and paradox somewhere, which I, as a professor drawing a full salary, was
    in duty bound to unravel and explain, if I could.

    So I meditated. And, first of all, I asked myself what the thing was that was
    so lacking in this Sabbatical city, and the lack of which kept one forever
    falling short of the higher sort of contentment. And I soon recognized that
    it was the element that gives to the wicked outer world all its moral style,
    expressiveness and picturesqueness,—the element of precipitousness, so
    to call it, of strength and strenuousness, intensity and danger. What ex-
    cites and interests the looker-on at life, what the romances and the statues

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 5

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    celebrate and the grim civic monuments remind us of, is the everlasting
    battle of the powers of light with those of darkness; with heroism, reduced
    to its bare chance, yet ever and anon snatching victory from the jaws of
    death. But in this unspeakable Chautauqua there was no potentiality of
    death in sight anywhere, and no point of the compass visible from which
    danger might possibly appear. The ideal was so completely victorious al-
    ready that no sign of any previous battle remained, the place just resting on
    its oars. But what our human emotions seem to require is the sight of the
    struggle going on. The moment the fruits are being merely eaten, things
    become ignoble. Sweat and effort, human nature strained to its uttermost
    and on the rack, yet getting through alive, and then turning its back on its
    success to pursue another more rare and arduous still—this is the sort of
    thing the presence of which inspires us, and the reality of which it seems
    to be the function of all the higher forms of literature and fine art to bring
    home to us and suggest. At Chautauqua there were no racks, even in the
    place’s historical museum; and no sweat, except possibly the gentle mois-
    ture on the brow of some lecturer, or on the sides of some player in the
    ball-field.

    Such absence of human naturein extremisanywhere seemed, then, a suf-
    ficient explanation for Chautauqua’s flatness and lack of zest.

    But was not this a paradox well calculated to fill one with dismay? It looks
    indeed, thought I, as if the romantic idealists with their pessimism about
    our civilization were, after all, quite right. An irremediable flatness is
    coming over the world. Bourgeoisie and mediocrity, church sociables and
    teachers’ conventions, are taking the place of the old heights and depths
    and romanticchiaroscuro. And, to get human life in its wild intensity, we
    must in future turn more and more away from the actual, and forget it, if
    we can, in the romancer’s or the poet’s pages. The whole world, delightful
    and sinful as it may still appear for a moment to one just escaped from
    the Chautauquan enclosure, is nevertheless obeying more and more just
    those ideals that are sure to make of it in the end a mere Chautauqua As-
    sembly on an enormous scale.Was im Gesang soll leben muss im Leben
    untergehn. Even now, in our own country, correctness, fairness, and com-
    promise for every small advantage are crowding out all other qualities.
    The higher heroisms and the old rare flavors are passing out of life.3

    With these thoughts in my mind, I was speeding with the train toward Buf-
    falo, when, near that city, the sight of a workman doing something on the

    3. This address was composed before the Cuban and Philippine wars. Such outbursts
    of the passion of mastery are, however, only episodes in a social process which in the
    long run seems everywhere heading toward the Chautauquan ideals.

    6 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    dizzy edge of a sky-scaling iron construction brought me to my senses very
    suddenly. And now I perceived, by a flash of insight, that I had been steep-
    ing myself in pure ancestral blindness, and looking at life with the eyes
    of a remote spectator. Wishing for heroism and the spectacle of human
    nature on the rack, I had never noticed the great fields of heroism lying
    round about me, I had failed to see it present and alive. I could only think
    of it as dead and embalmed, labelled and costumed, as it is in the pages of
    romance. And yet there it was before me in the daily lives of the laboring
    classes. Not in clanging fights and desperate marches only is heroism to
    be looked for, but on every railway bridge and fire-proof building that is
    going up to-day. On freight-trains, on the decks of vessels, in cattleyards
    and mines, on lumber-rafts, among the firemen and the policemen, the de-
    mand for courage is incessant; and the supply never fails. There, every day
    of the year somewhere, is human naturein extremisfor you. And wherever
    a scythe, an axe, a pick, or a shovel is wielded, you have it sweating and
    aching and with its powers of patient endurance racked to the utmost under
    the length of hours of the strain.

    From the reading. . .

    “An irremediable flatness is coming over the world. Bourgeoisie and
    mediocrity, church sociables and teachers’ conventions, are taking
    the place of the old heights and depths and romanticchiaroscuro. ”

    As I awoke to all this unidealized heroic life around me, the scales seemed
    to fall from my eyes; and a wave of sympathy greater than anything I had
    ever before felt with the common life of common men began to fill my
    soul. It began to seem as if virtue with horny hands and dirty skin were
    the only virtue genuine and vital enough to take account of. Every other
    virtue poses; none is absolutely unconscious and simple, and unexpectant
    of decoration or recognition, like this. These are our soldiers, thought I,
    these our sustainers, these the very parents of our life.

    Many years ago, when in Vienna, I had had a similar feeling of awe and
    reverence in looking at the peasant women, in from the country on their
    business at the market for the day. Old hags many of them were, dried
    and brown and wrinkled, kerchiefed and short-petticoated, with thick wool
    stockings on their bony shanks, stumping through the glittering thorough-
    fares, looking neither to the right nor the left, bent on duty, envying noth-
    ing, humble-hearted, remote;—and yet at bottom, when you came to think

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 7

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    of it, bearing the whole fabric of the splendors and corruptions of that city
    on their laborious backs. For where would any of it have been without
    their unremitting, unrewarded labor in the fields? And so with us: not to
    our generals and poets, I thought, but to the Italian and Hungarian laborers
    in the Subway, rather, ought the monuments of gratitude and reverence of
    a city like Boston to be reared.

    [Courage of the Everyday Person]
    If any of you have been readers of Tolstoï, you will see that I passed into
    a vein of feeling similar to his, with its abhorrence of all that convention-
    ally passes for distinguished, and its exclusive deification of the bravery,
    patience, kindliness, and dumbness of the unconscious natural man.

    Where now is our Tolstoï, I said, to bring the truth of all this home to our
    American bosoms, fill us with a better insight, and wean us away from that
    spurious literary romanticism on which our wretched culture-as it calls
    itself-is fed? Divinity lies all about us, and culture is too bide-bound to
    even suspect the fact. Could a Howells or a Kipling be enlisted in this mis-
    sion? or are they still too deep in the ancestral blindness, and not humane
    enough for the inner joy and meaning of the laborer’s existence to be really
    revealed? Must we wait for some one born and bred and living as a laborer
    himself, but who, by grace of Heaven, shall also find a literary voice?

    And there I rested on that day, with a sense of widening of vision, and
    with what it is surely fair to call an increase of religious insight into life.
    In God’s eyes the differences of social position, of intellect, of culture,
    of cleanliness, of dress, which different men exhibit? and all the other
    rarities and exceptions on which they so fantastically pin their pride, must
    be so small as practically quite to vanish; and all that should remain is
    the common fact that here we are, a countless multitude of vessels of life,
    each of us pent in to peculiar difficulties, with which we must severally
    struggle by using whatever of fortitude and goodness we can summon up.
    The exercise of the courage, patience, and kindness, must be the significant
    portion of the whole business; and the distinctions of position can only
    be a manner of diversifying the phenomenal surface upon which these
    underground virtues may manifest their effects. At this rate, the deepest
    human life is everywhere, is eternal. And, if any human attributes exist
    only in particular individuals, they must belong to the mere trapping and
    decoration of the surface-show.

    8 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    Thus are men’s lives levelled up as well as levelled down,—levelled up
    in their common inner meaning, levelled down in their outer gloriousness
    and show. Yet always, we must confess, this levelling insight tends to be
    obscured again; and always the ancestral blindness returns and wraps us
    up, so that we end once more by thinking that creation can be for no other
    purpose than to develop remarkable situations and conventional distinc-
    tions and merits. And then always some new leveller in the shape of a reli-
    gious prophet has to arise—the Buddha, the Christ, or some Saint Francis,
    some Rousseau or Tolstoï—to redispel our blindness. Yet, little by little,
    there comes some stable gain; for the world does get more humane, and
    the religion of democracy tends toward permanent increase.

    This, as I said, became for a time my conviction, and gave me great con-
    tent. I have put the matter into the form of a personal reminiscence, so that
    I might lead you into it more directly and completely, and so save time.
    But now I am going to discuss the rest of it with you in a more impersonal
    way.

    Three Peasants Walking to Market, Library of Congress

    Tolstoï’s levelling philosophy began long before he had the crisis of melan-
    choly commemorated in that wonderful document of his entitledMy Con-
    fession,which led the way to his more specifically religious works. In
    his masterpieceWar and Peace,—assuredly the greatest of human nov-

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 9

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    els,—the rôle of the spiritual hero is given to a poor little soldier named
    Karataïeff, so helpful, so cheerful, and so devout that, in spite of his igno-
    rance and filthiness, the sight of him opens the heavens, which have been
    closed, to the mind of the principal character of the book; and his exam-
    ple evidently is meant by Tolstoï to let God into the world again for the
    reader. Poor little Karataïeff is taken prisoner by the French; and, when
    too exhausted by hardship and fever to march, is shot as other prisoners
    were in the famous retreat from Moscow. The last view one gets of him
    is his little figure leaning against a white birch-tree, and uncomplainingly
    awaiting the end.

    “The more,” writes Tolstoï in the workMy Confession,“the more I ex-
    amined the life of these laboring folks, the more persuaded I became that
    they veritably have faith, and get from it alone the sense and the possibil-
    ity of life.. . . Contrariwise to those of our own class, who protest against
    destiny and grow indignant at its rigor, these people receive maladies and
    misfortunes without revolt, without opposition, and with a firm and tran-
    quil confidence that all had to be like that, could not be otherwise, and that
    it is all right so.. . . The more we live by our intellect, the less we under-
    stand the meaning of life. We see only a cruel jest in suffering and death,
    whereas these people live, suffer, and draw near to death with tranquillity,
    and oftener than not with joy.. . . There are enormous multitudes of them
    happy with the most perfect happiness, although deprived of what for us is
    the sole of good of life. Those who understand life’s meaning, and know
    how to live and die thus, are to be counted not by twos, threes, tens, but by
    hundreds, thousands, millions. They labor quietly, endure privations and
    pains, live and die, and throughout everything see the good without seeing
    the vanity. I had to love these people. The more I entered into their life, the
    more I loved them; and the more it became possible for me to live, too. It
    came about not only that the life of our society, of the learned and of the
    rich, disgusted me—more than that, it lost all semblance of meaning in my
    eyes. All our actions, our deliberations, our sciences, our arts, all appeared
    to me with a new significance. I understood that these things might be
    charming pastimes, but that one need seek in them no depth, whereas the
    life of the hardworking populace, of that multitude of human beings who
    really contribute to existence, appeared to me in its true light. I understood
    that there veritably is life, that the meaning which life there receives is the
    truth; and I accepted it.”4

    In a similar way does Stevenson appeal to our piety toward the elemental
    virtue of mankind.

    4. My Confession, X. (condensed).

    10 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    “What a wonderful thing,” he writes,5 “is this Man! How surprising are his
    attributes! Poor soul, here for so little, cast among so many hardships, sav-
    agely surrounded, savagely descended, irremediably condemned to prey
    upon his fellow-lives,—who should have blamed him, had be been of a
    piece with his destiny and a being merely barbarous?. . . [Yet] it matters
    not where we look, under what climate we observe him, in what stage
    of society, in what depth of ignorance, burdened with what erroneous
    morality; in ships at sea, a man inured to hardship and vile pleasures, his
    brightest hope a fiddle in a tavern, and a bedizened trull who sells herself
    to rob him, and be, for all that, simple, innocent, cheerful, kindly like a
    child, constant to toil, brave to drown, for others;. . . in the slums of cities,
    moving among indifferent millions to mechanical employments, without
    hope of change in the future, with scarce a pleasure in the present, and yet
    true to his virtues, honest up to his lights, kind to his neighbors, tempted
    perhaps in vain by the bright gin-palace,. . . often repaying the world’s
    scorn with service, often standing firm upon a scruple;. . . everywhere
    some virtue cherished or affected, everywhere some decency of thought
    and courage, everywhere the ensign of man’s ineffectual goodness,—ah!
    if I could show you this! If I could show you these men and women all
    the world over, in every stage of history, under every abuse of error, under
    every circumstance of failure, without hope, without help, without thanks,
    still obscurely fighting the lost fight of virtue, still clinging to some rag of
    honor, the poor jewel of their souls.”

    All this is as true as it is splendid, and terribly do we need our Tolstoïs and
    Stevensons to keep our sense for it alive. Yet you remember the Irishman
    who, when asked, “Is not one man as good as another?” replied, “Yes;
    and a great deal better, too!” Similarly (it seems to me) does Tolstoï over-
    correct our social prejudices, when he makes his love of the peasant so
    exclusive, and hardens his heart toward the educated man as absolutely
    as he does. Grant that at Chautauqua there was little moral effort, little
    sweat or muscular strain in view. Still, deep down in the souls of the par-
    ticipants we may be sure that something of the sort was hid, some inner
    stress, some vital virtue not found wanting when required. And, after all,
    the question recurs, and forces itself upon us, Is it so certain that the sur-
    roundings and circumstances of the virtue do make so little difference in
    the importance of the result? Is the functional utility, the worth to the uni-
    verse of a certain definite amount of courage, kindliness, and patience, no
    greater if the possessor of these virtues is in an educated situation, working
    out far-reaching tasks, than if he be an illiterate nobody, hewing wood and

    5. Across the Plains: “Pulvis et Umbra” (abridged).

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 11

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    drawing water, just to keep himself alive? Tolstoï’s philosophy, deeply en-
    lightening though it certainly is, remains a false abstraction. It savors too
    much of that Oriental pessimism and nihilism of his, which declares the
    whole phenomenal world and its facts and their distinctions to be a cun-
    ning fraud.

    Switchtender on Pennsylvania Railroad, Library of Congress

    [Ideas of Individuals]
    A mere bare fraud is just what our Western common sense will never be-
    lieve the phenomenal world to be. It admits fully that the inner joys and
    virtues are theessentialpart of life’s business, but it is sure that some
    positive part is also played by the adjuncts of the show. If it is idiotic
    in romanticism to recognize the heroic only when it sees it labelled and
    dressed-up in books, it is really just as idiotic to see it only in the dirty
    boots and sweaty shirt of some one in the fields. It is with us really under
    every disguise: at Chautauqua; here in your college; in the stock-yards and
    on the freight-trains; and in the czar of Russia’s court. But, instinctively,
    we make a combination of two things in judging the total significance of
    a human being. We feel it to be some sort of a product (if such a product
    only could be calculated) of his inner virtueand his outer place,—neither
    singly taken, but both conjoined. If the outer differences had no meaning
    for life, why indeed should all this immense variety of them exist? They

    12 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    must be significant elements of the world as well.

    Just test Tolstoï’s deification of the mere manual laborer by the facts. This
    is what Mr. Walter Wyckoff, after working as an unskilled laborer in the
    demolition of some buildings at West Point, writes of the spiritual condi-
    tion of the class of men to which he temporarily chose to belong:—

    The salient features of our condition are plain enough. We are grown men,
    and are without a trade. In the labor-market we stand ready to sell to the
    highest bidder our mere muscular strength for so many hours each day. We
    are thus in the lowest grade of labor. And, selling our muscular strength in
    the open market for what it will bring, we sell it under peculiar conditions. It
    is all the capital that we have. We have no reserve means of subsistence, and
    cannot, therefore, stand off for a “reserve price.” We sell under the necessity
    of satisfying imminent hunger. Broadly speaking, we must sell our labor or
    starve; and, as hunger is a matter of a few hours, and we have no other way
    of meeting this need, we must sell at once for what the market offers for our
    labor.

    Our employer is buying labor in a dear market, and be will certainly get from
    us as much work as he can at the price. The gang-boss is secured for this
    purpose, and thoroughly does he know his business. He has sole command
    of us. He never saw us before, and he will discharge us all when the debris is
    cleared away. In the mean time he must get from us, if he can, the utmost of
    physical labor which we, individually and collectively, are capable of. If be
    should drive some of us to exhaustion, and we should not be able to continue
    at work, he would not be the loser; for the market would soon supply him
    with others to take our places.

    We are ignorant men, but so much we clearly see,—that we have sold our
    labor where we could sell it dearest, and our employer has bought it where be
    could buy it cheapest. He has paid high, and be must get all the labor that he
    can; and, by a strong instinct which possesses us, we shall part with as little
    as we can. From work like ours there seems to us to have been eliminated
    every element which constitutes the nobility of labor. We feel no personal
    pride in its progress, and no community of interest with our employer. There
    is none of the joy of responsibility, none of the sense of achievement, only
    the dull monotony of grinding toil, with the longing for the signal to quit
    work, and for our wages at the end.

    And being what we are, the dregs of the labor-market, and having no certainty
    of permanent employment, and no organization among ourselves, we must
    expect to work under the watchful eye of a gang-boss, and be driven, like the
    wage-slaves that we are, through our tasks.

    All this is to tell us, in effect, that our lives are hard, barren, hopeless lives.

    And such bard, barren, hopeless lives, surely, are not lives in which one

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 13

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    ought to be willing permanently to remain. And why is this so? Is it be-
    cause they are so dirty? Well, Nansen grew a great deal dirtier on his polar
    expedition; and we think none the worse of his life for that. Is it the insen-
    sibility? Our soldiers have to grow vastly more insensible, and we extol
    them to the skies. Is it the poverty? Poverty has been reckoned the crown-
    ing beauty of many a heroic career. Is it the slavery to a task, the loss
    of finer pleasures? Such slavery and loss are of the very essence of the
    higher fortitude, and are always counted to its credit,—read the records of
    missionary devotion all over the world. It is not any one of these things,
    then, taken by itself,—no, nor all of them together,—that make such a life
    undesirable. A man might in truth live like an unskilled laborer, and do
    the work of one, and yet count as one of the noblest of God’s creatures.
    Quite possibly there were some such persons in the gang that our author
    describes; but the current of their souls ran underground; and he was too
    steeped in the ancestral blindness to discern it.

    Steelworker with Daughter, Ambridge, Pennsylvania, Library of Congress

    If there were any such morally exceptional individuals, however, what
    made them different from the rest? It can only have been this,—that their
    souls worked and endured in obedience to some innerideal, while their
    comrades were not actuated by anything worthy of that name. These ideals
    of other lives are among those secrets that we can almost never penetrate,

    14 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    although something about the man may often tell us when they are there.
    In Mr. Wyckoff’s own case we know exactly what the self-imposed ideal
    was. Partly he had stumped himself, as the boys say, to carry through a
    strenuous achievement; but mainly he wished to enlarge his sympathetic
    insight into fellow-lives. For this his sweat and toil acquire a certain heroic
    significance, and make us accord to him exceptional esteem. But it is
    easy to imagine his fellows with various other ideals. To say nothing of
    wives and babies, one may have been a convert of the Salvation Army,
    and bad a nightingale singing of expiation and forgiveness in his heart all
    the while be labored. Or there might have been an apostle like Tolstoï him-
    self, or his compatriot Bondaïeff, in the gang, voluntarily embracing labor
    as their religious mission. Class-loyalty was undoubtedly an ideal with
    many. And who knows how much of that higher manliness of poverty, of
    which Phillips Brooks has spoken so penetratingly, was or was not present
    in that gang?

    “A rugged, barren land,” says Phillips Brooks, “is poverty to live in,—a
    land where I am thankful very often if I can get a berry or a root to cat. But
    living in it really, letting it bear witness to me of itself, not dishonoring it
    all the time by judging it after the standard of the other lands, gradually
    there come out its qualities. Behold! no land like this barren and naked
    land of poverty could show the moral geology of the world. See how the
    hard ribs. . . stand out strong and solid. No life like poverty could so get
    one to the heart of things and make men know their meaning, could so let
    us feel life and the world with all the soft cushions stripped off and thrown
    away. . . . Poverty makes men come very near each other, and recognize
    each other’s human hearts; and poverty, highest and best of all, demands
    and cries out for faith in God. . . . I know how superficial and unfeeling,
    how like mere mockery, words in praise of poverty may seem. . . . But I am
    sure that the poor man’s dignity and freedom, his self-respect and energy,
    depend upon his cordial knowledge that his poverty is a true region and
    kind of life, with its own chances of character, its own springs of happiness
    and revelations of God. Let him resist the characterlessness which often
    goes with being poor. Let him insist on respecting the condition where he
    lives. Let him learn to love it, so that by and by, [if] he grows rich, he
    shall go out of the low door of the old familiar poverty with a true pang of
    regret, and with a true honor for the narrow home in which he has lived so
    long.”6

    The barrenness and ignobleness of the more usual laborer’s life consist in
    the fact that it is moved by no such ideal inner springs. The backache, the

    6. Sermons, 5th Series, New York, 1893, pp. 166, 167.

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 15

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    long hours, the danger, are patiently endured-for what? To gain a quid of
    tobacco, a glass of beer, a cup of coffee, a meal, and a bed, and to begin
    again the next day and shirk as much as one can. This really is why we
    raise no monument to the laborers in the Subway, even though they be out
    conscripts, and even though after a fashion our city is indeed based upon
    their patient hearts and enduring backs and shoulders. And this is why we
    do raise monuments to our soldiers, whose outward conditions were even
    brutaller still. The soldiers are supposed to have followed an ideal, and the
    laborers are supposed to have followed none.

    From the reading. . .

    “If there were any such morally exceptional individuals, however,
    what made them different from the rest?”

    You see, my friends, how the plot now thickens; and how strangely the
    complexities of this wonderful human nature of ours begin to develop un-
    der our hands. We have seen the blindness and deadness to each other
    which are our natural inheritance; and, in spite of them, we have been led
    to acknowledge an inner meaning which passeth show, and which may be
    present in the lives of others where we least descry it. And now we are led
    to say that such inner meaning can becompleteand valid for us also, only
    when the inner joy, courage, and endurance are joined with an ideal.

    [Ideals]
    But what, exactly, do we mean by an ideal? Can we give no definite ac-
    count of such a word?

    To a certain extent we can. An ideal, for instance, must be something in-
    tellectually conceived, something of which we are not unconscious, if we
    have it; and it must carry with it that sort of outlook, uplift, and brightness
    that go with all intellectual facts. Secondly, there must benoveltyin an
    ideal,—novelty at least for him whom the ideal grasps. Sodden routine is
    incompatible with ideality, although what is sodden routine for one person
    may be ideal novelty for another. This shows that there is nothing abso-
    lutely ideal: ideals are relative to the lives that entertain them. To keep out
    of the gutter is for us here no part of consciousness at all, yet for many of
    our brethren it is the most legitimately engrossing of ideals.

    16 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    Now, taken nakedly, abstractly, and immediately, you see that mere ide-
    als are the cheapest things in life. Everybody has them in some shape
    or other, personal or general, sound or mistaken, low or high; and the
    most worthless sentimentalists and dreamers, drunkards, shirks and verse-
    makers, who never show a grain of effort, courage, or endurance, possibly
    have them on the most copious scale. Education, enlarging as it does our
    horizon and perspective, is a means of multiplying our ideals, of bring-
    ing new ones into view. And your college professor, with a starched shirt
    and spectacles, would, if a stock of ideals were all alone by itself enough
    to render a life significant, be the most absolutely and deeply significant
    of men. Tolstoï would be completely blind in despising him for a prig, a
    pedant and a parody; and all our new insight into the divinity of muscular
    labor would be altogether off the track of truth.

    But such consequences as this, you instinctively feel, are erroneous. The
    more ideals a man has, the more contemptible, on the whole, do you con-
    tinue to deem him, if the matter ends there for him, and if none of the labor-
    ing man’s virtues are called into action on his part,—no courage shown, no
    privations undergone, no dirt or scars contracted in the attempt to get them
    realized. It is quite obvious that something more than the mere possession
    of ideals is required to make a life significant in any sense that claims the
    spectator’s admiration. Inner joy, to be sure, it mayhave, with its ideals;
    but that is its own private sentimental matter. To extort from us, outsiders
    as we are, with our own ideals to look after, the tribute of our grudging
    recognition, it must back its ideal visions with what the laborers have, the
    sterner stuff of manly virtue; it must multiply their sentimental surface by
    the dimension of the active will, if we are to havedepth, if we are to have
    anything cubical and solid in the way of character.

    The significance of a human life for communicable and publicly recogniz-
    able purposes is thus the offspring of a marriage of two different parents,
    either of whom alone is barren. The ideals taken by themselves give no
    reality, the virtues by themselves no novelty. And let the orientalists and
    pessimists say what they will, the thing of deepest—or, at any rate, of
    comparatively deepest—significance in life does seem to be its character
    of progress, or that strange union of reality with ideal novelty which it
    continues from one moment to another to present. To recognize ideal nov-
    elty is the task of what we call intelligence. Not every one’s intelligence
    can tell which novelties are ideal. For many the ideal thing will always
    seem to cling still to the older more familiar good. In this case character,
    though not significant totally, may be still significant pathetically. So, if we
    are to choose which is the more essential factor of human character, the

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 17

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    fighting virtue or the intellectual breadth, we must side with Tolstoï, and
    choose that simple faithfulness to his light or darkness which any common
    unintellectual man can show.

    Harvard Gate, Harvard College, Library of Congress

    [Culture, Courage, Ideals, and Joyful
    Sympathy]
    But, with all this beating and tacking on my part, I fear you take me to be
    reaching a confused result. I seem to be just taking things up and dropping
    them again. First I took up Chautauqua, and dropped that; then Tolstoï
    and the heroism of common toil, and dropped them; finally, I took up
    ideals, and seem now almost dropping those. But please observe in what
    sense it is that I drop them. It is when they pretend singly to redeem life
    from insignificance. Culture and refinement all alone are not enough to
    do so. Ideal aspirations are not enough, when uncombined with pluck and
    will. But neither are pluck and will, dogged endurance and insensibility to
    danger enough, when taken all alone. There must be some sort of fusion,
    some chemical combination among these principles, for a life objectively
    and thoroughly significant to result.

    Of course, this is a somewhat vague conclusion. But in a question of sig-
    nificance, of worth, like this, conclusions can never be precise. The answer
    of appreciation, of sentiment, is always a more or a less, a balance struck

    18 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    by sympathy, insight, and good will. But it is an answer, all the same a real
    conclusion. And, in the course of getting it, it seems to me that our eyes
    have been opened to many important things. Some of you are, perhaps,
    more livingly aware than you were an hour ago of the depths of worth that
    lie around you, hid in alien lives. And, when you ask how much sympathy
    you ought to bestow, although the amount is, truly enough, a matter of
    ideal on your own part, yet in this notion of the combination of ideals with
    active virtues you have a rough standard for shaping your decision. In any
    case, your imagination is extended. You divine in the world about you mat-
    ter for a little more humility on your own part, and tolerance, reverence,
    and love for others; and you gain a certain inner joyfulness at the increased
    importance of our common life. Such joyfulness is a religious inspiration
    and an element of spiritual health, and worth more than large amounts of
    that sort of technical and accurate information which we professors are
    supposed to be able to impart.

    [One Last Example]
    To show the sort of thing I mean by these words, I will just make one brief
    practical illustration, and then close.

    We are suffering to-day in America from what is called the labor-question;
    and, when you go out into the world, you will each and all of you be caught
    up in its perplexities. I use the brief term labor-question to cover all sorts
    of anarchistic discontents and socialistic projects, and the conservative re-
    sistances which they provoke. So far as this conflict is unhealthy and re-
    grettable,—and I think it is so only to a limited extent,—the unhealthiness
    consists solely in the fact that one-half of our fellow countrymen remain
    entirely blind to the internal significance of the lives of the other half. They
    miss the joys and sorrows, they fail to feel the moral virtue, and they do not
    guess the presence of the intellectual ideals. They are at cross-purposes all
    along the line, regarding each other as they might regard a set of danger-
    ously gesticulating automata, or, if they seek to get at the inner motivation,
    making the most horrible mistakes. Often all that the poor man can think
    of in the rich man is a cowardly greediness for safety, luxury, and effemi-
    nacy, and a boundless affectation. What he is, is not a human being, but a
    pocket-book, a bank-account. And a similar greediness, turned by disap-
    pointment into envy, is all that many rich men can see in the state of mind
    of the dissatisfied poor. And, if the rich man begins to do the sentimen-
    tal act over the poor man, what senseless blunders does he make, pitying

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 19

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    him for just those very duties and those very immunities which, rightly
    taken, are the condition of his most abiding and characteristic joys! Each,
    in short, ignores the fact that happiness and unhappiness and significance
    are a vital mystery; each pins them absolutely on some ridiculous fea-
    ture of the external situation; and everybody remains outside of everybody
    else’s sight.

    Society has, with all this, undoubtedly got to pass toward some newer and
    better equilibrium, and the distribution of wealth has doubtless slowly got
    to change: such changes have always happened, and will happen to the
    end of time. But if, after all that I have said, any of you expect that they
    will make anygenuine vital differenceon a large scale, to the lives of our
    descendants, you will have missed the significance of my entire lecture.
    The solid meaning of life is always the same eternal thing,—the marriage,
    namely, of some unhabitual ideal, however special, with some fidelity,
    courage, and endurance; with some man’s or woman’s pains.—And, what-
    ever or wherever life may be, there will always be the chance for that mar-
    riage to take place.

    Fitz-James Stephen wrote many years ago words to this effect more elo-
    quent than any I can speak: “The ‘Great Eastern,’ or some of her succes-
    sors,” he said, “will perhaps defy the roll of the Atlantic, and cross the seas
    without allowing their passengers to feel that they have left the firm land.
    The voyage from the cradle to the grave may come to be performed with
    similar facility. Progress and science may perhaps enable untold millions
    to live and die without a care, without a pang, without an anxiety. They
    will have a pleasant passage and plenty of brilliant conversation. They will
    wonder that men ever believed at all in clanging fights and blazing towns
    and sinking ships and praying bands; and, when they come to the end of
    their course, they will go their way, and the place thereof will know them
    no more. But it seems unlikely that they will have such a knowledge of
    the great ocean on which they sail, with its storms and wrecks, its currents
    and icebergs, its huge waves and mighty winds, as those who battled with
    it for years together in the little craft, which, if they had few other merits,
    brought those who navigated them full into the presence of time and eter-
    nity, their maker and themselves, and forced them to have some definite
    view of their relations to them and to each other.”7

    7. Essays by a Barrister, London, 1862, p. 318.

    20 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    Harvard Medical College, Boston, Mass., Library of Congress

    In this solid and tridimensional sense, so to call it, those philosophers are
    right who contend that the world is a standing thing, with no progress, no
    real history. The changing conditions of history touch only the surface of
    the show. The altered equilibriums and redistributions only diversify our
    opportunities and open chances to us for new ideals. But, with each new
    ideal that comes into life, the chance for a life based on some old ideal
    will vanish; and he would needs be a presumptuous calculator who should
    with confidence say that the total sum of significances is positively and
    absolutely greater at any one epoch than at any other of the world.

    I am speaking broadly, I know, and omitting to consider certain qualifi-
    cations in which I myself believe. But one can only make one point in
    one lecture, and I shall be well content if I have brought my point home
    to you this evening in even a slight degree.There are compensationsand
    no outward changes of condition in life can keep the nightingale of its
    eternal meaning from singing in all sorts of different men’s hearts. That
    is the main fact to remember. If we could not only admit it with our lips,
    but really and truly believe it, how our convulsive insistencies, how our
    antipathies and dreads of each other, would soften down! If the poor and
    the rich could look at each other in this way,sub specie æternatis, How
    gentle would grow their disputes! what tolerance and good humor, what
    willingness to live and let live, would come into the world!

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 21

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James
    From the reading. . .

    “Now, taken nakedly, abstractly, and immediately, you see that mere
    ideals are the cheapest things in life. Everybody has them in some
    shape or other, personal or general, sound or mistaken, low or high;
    and the most worthless sentimentalists and dreamers, drunkards,
    shirks and verse-makers, who never show a grain of effort, courage,
    or endurance, possibly have them on the most copious scale. ”

    Related Ideas
    William James(http://www.emory.edu/EDUCATION/mfp/james.html). Links,
    articles, etexts, reviews, and discussion groups are part of what make up
    this extensive James site.

    Classics in the History of Psychology(http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/). York
    University History & Theory of Psychology Electronic Resource. Special
    collections, extensive open-domain readings in the history of psychology
    searchable by author or title, and suggested readings.

  • Index
  • Agassiz, Louis,1
    anarchists,19
    Brooks, Phillips,15
    character,17
    culture,18
    emotion

    greed,19
    friendship,3
    history

    progress,21
    ideals,16
    James, William,1

    22 Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction

    “What Makes a Life Significant?” by William James

    joy, 19
    love, 2
    middle class,4
    nihilism, 12
    pessimism,12
    philosophy

    Oriental,17
    practical person,7
    pragmatism,1
    prophets,9
    slave-morality,14
    tolerance,2
    Tolstoy, Leo,9
    Utopia,5
    values,2
    virtue, 11, 19

    Reading For Philosophical Inquiry: A Brief Introduction 23

    • What Makes a Life Significant? by William James
    • The Selection from What Makes Life a Significant?
    • [Life’s Values and Meanings]
      [Courage of the Everyday Person]
      [Ideas of Individuals]
      [Ideals]
      [Culture, Courage, Ideals, and Joyful Sympathy]
      [One Last Example]
      Related Ideas
      Index

    Chapter 10

    The Nature of Mental States

    Hilary Putnam

    The typical concerns of the Philosopher of Mind might be represented by three questions
    : (1) How do we know that other people have pains? (2) Are pains brain states?

    (3) What is the analysis of the concept pain? I do not wish to discuss questions (1) and
    (3) in this chapter. I shall say something about question (2).

    Identity Questions

    is pain a brain stater (Or, is the property of having a pain at time t a brain stater)
    ! It is

    impossible to discuss this question sensibly without saying something about the peculiar
    rules which have grown up in the course of the development of

    analytical philoso

    phy
    ‘- rules which, far from leading to an end to all conceptual confusions, themselves

    represent considerable conceptual confusion. These rules- which are, of course, implicit
    rather than explicit in the practice of most analytical philosophers- are (1) that a

    statement of the form ‘ being A is being B

    (e.g., ‘ being in pain is being in a certain brain

    state’) can be corred only if it follows, in some sense, from the meaning of the terms
    A and B; and (2) that a statement of the form ‘ being A is being B can be philosophically
    infonnatit1e only if it is in some sense reductive (e.g., ‘ being in pain is having a certain
    unpleasant sensation

    ‘ is not philosophically informative; ‘ being in pain is having a
    certain behavior disposition

    ‘ is, if true, philosophically informative). These rules are
    excellent rules if we still believe that the program of reductive analysis (in the style of
    the 1930s) can be carried out; if we don

    ‘t, then they turn analytical philosophy into
    a mug

    ‘s game, at least so far as
    ‘is’ questions are concerned.

    In this paper I shall use the term


    property

    ‘ as a blanket term for such things as being
    in pain, being in a particular brain state, having a particular behavior disposition, and
    also for magnitudes such as temperature, etc.- i.e., for things which can naturally be

    represented by one- or-more-place predicates or functors. I shall use the term

    concept

    for things which can be identified with synonymy-classes of expressions. Thus the

    concept temperature can be identified a maintain) with the synonymy-class of the word


    temperature

    ‘.2 (This is like saying that the number 2 can be identified with the class of
    all pairs. This is quite a different statement from the peculiar statement that 2 is the class
    of all pairs. I do not maintain that concepts are synonymy-classes, whatever that might
    mean, but that they can be identified with synonymy-classes, for the purpose of formal-
    ization of the relevant discourse.)

    The question What is the concept temperaturer is a very

    funny

    ‘ one. One might take
    it to mean What is temperature? Please take my question as a conceptual one.

    ‘ In that
    case an answer might be (pretend for a moment ‘ heat

    ‘ and ‘temperature
    ‘ are synonyms)’

    temperature is heat

    , or even

    ‘the concept of temperature is the same concept as the
    concept of heat

    ‘. Or one might take it to mean What are concepf$, really? For example,
    what is “the concept of temperature

    ‘7 In that case heaven knows what an ‘answer’

    52 Hilary Putnam

    would be. ( perhaps it would be the statement that concepts can be identified with
    synonymy-c Iasses.)

    Of course, the question What is the property temperaturef is also

    funny

    ‘. And one
    way of interpreting it is to take it as a question about the concept of temperature. But
    this is not the way a physicist would take it .

    The effect of saying that the property PI can be identical with the property P2 only if
    the terms PI, P2 are in some suitable sense


    synonyms

    ‘ is, to all intents and purposes,
    to collapse the two notions of


    property

    ‘ and ‘concept

    into a single notion. The view

    that concepts (intensions) are the same as properties has been explicitly advocated by
    Camap (e.g., in Meaning and Necessity). This seems an unfortunate view, since


    temperature

    is mean molecular kinetic energy

    appears to be a perfectly good example of a true

    statement of identity of properties, whereas
    ‘the concept of temperature is the same

    concept as a concept of mean molecular kinetic energy
    ‘ is simply false.

    Many philosophers believe that the statement

    pain is a brain state

    ‘ violates some
    rules or norms of English. But the arguments offered are hardly convincing. For example

    , if the fact that I can know that I am in pain without knowing that I am in brain state
    S shows that pain cannot be brain state S, then, by exactly the same argument, the fact
    that I can know that the stove is hot without knowing that the mean molecular kinetic
    energy is high (or even that molecules exist) shows that it is false that temperature is
    mean molecular kinetic energy, physics to the contrary. In fact, all that immediately
    follows from the fact that I can know that I am in pain without knowing that I am in
    brain state S is that the concept of pain is not the same concept as the concept of being
    in brain state S. But either p~ or the state of being in p~ or some p~ or some pain
    state, might still be brain state S. After all, the concept of temperature is not the same
    concept as the concept of mean molecular kinetic energy. But temperature is mean
    molecular kinetic energy.

    Some philosophers maintain that both

    pain is a brain state

    ‘ and ‘pain states are brain
    states’ are unintelligible. The answer is to explain to these philosophers, as well as we
    can, given the vagueness of all scientific methodology, what sorts of considerations
    lead one to make an empirical reduction (i.e., to say such things as

    ‘water is H2O

    , ‘light

    is electromagnetic radiation

    ,


    temperature is mean molecular kinetic energy


    ). If, without

    giving reasons, he still maintains in the face of such examples that one cannot
    imagine parallel circumstances for the use of


    pains are brain states


    (or, perhaps,


    pain

    states are brain states’), one has grounds to regard him as perverse.
    Some philosophers maintain that


    PI is P2

    ‘ is something that can be true, when the’is’ involved is the ‘is’ of empirical reduction, only when the properties PI and P 2 are
    (a) associated with a spatio- temporal region; and (b) the region is one and the same in
    both cases. Thus ‘temperature is mean molecular kinetic energy

    ‘ is an admissible empirical
    reduction, since the temperature and the molecular energy are associated with the

    same space-time region, but ‘ having a pain in my arm is being in a brain state
    ‘ is not,

    since the spatial regions involved are different.
    This argument does not appear very strong. Surely no one is going to be deterred

    from saying that mirror images are light reflected from an object and then from the
    surface of a mirror by the fact that an image can be 1ocated

    ‘ three feet behind the
    mirror! ( Moreover, one can always Bnd some common property of the reductions one is
    willing to allow- e.g., temperature is mean molecular kinetic energy- which is not
    a property of some one identification one wishes to disallow. This is not very impressive

    unless one has an argument to show that the very purposes of such identification
    depend upon the common property in question.)

    Again , other philosophers have contended that all the predictions that can be derived
    &om the conjunction of neurophysiological laws with such statements as


    pain

    states are such-and-such brain states

    can equally well be derived &om the conjunction

    of the same neurophysiological laws with ‘ being in pain is correlated with such
    -and-

    such brain states

    , and hence (sic!) there can be no methodological grounds for saying

    that pains (or pain states) are brain states, as opposed to saying that they are correlated

    (invariantly ) with brain states. This argument , too , would show that light is only correlated
    with electromagnetic radiation . The mistake is in ignoring the fact that , although

    the theories in question may indeed lead to the same predictions , they open and
    exclude different questions.


    Ught is invariantly correlated with electromagnetic radia

    tion

    would leave open the questions What is the light then, if it isn

    t the same as the

    electromagnetic radiationr and What makes the light accompany the electromagnetic
    radiation ?

    ‘ –
    questions which are excluded by saying that the light is the electromagnetic

    radiation . Similarly , the purpose of saying that pains are brain states is precisely to
    exclude from empirical meaningfulness the questions What is the pain, then, if it isn


    t

    the same as the brain stater and What makes the pain accompany the brain state?

    If
    there are grounds to suggest that these questions represent, so to speak, the wrong way
    to look at the matter , then those grounds are grounds for a theoretical identification of

    pains with brain states.
    If all arguments to the contrary are unconvincing , shall we then conclude that it is

    meaningful (and perhaps true ) to say either that pains are brain states or that pain states
    are brain states?

    1. It is perfectly meaningful (violates no

    rule of English


    , involves no


    extension

    of usage

    ) to say


    pains are brain states


    .

    2. It is not meaningful (involves a

    changing of meaning


    or


    an extension of

    usage

    , etc.) to say


    pains are brain states

    .

    My own position is not expressed by either 1 or 2. It seems to me that the notions’
    change of meaning


    and


    extension of usage


    are simply so ill defined that one cannot in

    fact say either 1 or 2. I see no reason to believe that either the linguist , or the man-on –

    the-street, or the philosopher possess es today a notion of

    change of meaning


    applicable

    to such cases as the one we have been discussing. The job for which the notion of

    change of meaning was developed in the history of the language was just a much cruder

    job than this one.
    But, if we don


    t assert either 1 or 2- in other words , if we regard the


    change of

    meaning

    issue as a pseudoissue in this case

    – then how are we to discuss the question
    with which we started?


    Is pain a brain stater

    The answer is to allow statements of the form

    pain is A


    , where


    pain

    and


    A


    are in

    no sense synonyms , and to see whether any such statement can be found which might
    be acceptable on empirical and methodological grounds . This is what we shall now

    proceed to do .

    Is Pain a Brain State?

    We shall discuss is pain a brain stater then . And we have agreed to waive the

    change

    of meaning

    issue.

    Since I am discussing not what the concept of pain comes to , but what pain is, in a
    sense of


    is


    which requires empirical theory – construdion (or , at least, empirical speculation

    ), I shall not apologize for advancing an empirical hypothesis . Indeed, my strategy

    The Nature of Mental States S3

    S4 Hilary Putnam

    will be to argue that pain is not a brain state, not on a priori grounds, but on the
    grounds that another hypothesis is more plausible. The detailed development and
    verification of my hypothesis would be just as Utopian a task as the detailed development

    and verification of the brain-state hypothesis. But the putting-forward, not of
    detailed and scientifically

    ‘finished’ hypotheses, but of schemata for hypotheses, has
    long been a function of philosophy. I shall, in short, argue that pain is not a brain
    state, in the sense of a physical-chemical state of the brain (or even the whole nervous
    system), but another kind of state entirely. I propose the hypothesis that pain, or the
    state of being in pain, is a functional state of a whole organism.

    To explain this it is necessary to introduce some technical notions. In previous papers
    I have explained the notion of a Turing Machine and discussed the use of this notion
    as a model for an organism. The notion of a Probabilistic Automaton is de Aned similarly
    to a Turing Machine, except that the transitions between

    ‘states’ are allowed to be
    with various probabilities rather than being

    ‘deterministic’. (Of course, a Turing
    Machine is simply a special kind of Probabilistic Automaton, one with transition prob-
    abilities 0, 1). I shall assume the notion of a Probabilistic Automaton has been generalized

    to allow for ‘sensory inputs
    ‘ and ‘motor outputs

    ‘- that is, the Machine Table
    specifies, for every possible combination of a

    ‘state’ and a complete set of

    sensory

    inputs

    , an

    ‘instruction’ which determines the probability of the next
    ‘state’, and also the

    probabilities of the
    ‘motor outputs

    ‘. ( This replaces the idea of the Machine as printing
    on a tape.) I shall also assume that the physical realization of the sense organs responsible

    for the various inputs, and of the motor organs, is specified, but that the

    states’

    and the ‘inputs
    ‘ themselves are, as usual, specified only


    implicitly

    ‘- i.e., by the set of
    transition probabilities given by the Machine Table.

    Since an empirically given system can simultaneously be a

    physical realization

    ‘ of
    many different Probabilistic Automata, I introduce the notion of a Description of a
    system. A Description of 5 where 5 is a system, is any true statement to the effect that 5
    possess es distinct states 51, 51, . . . ~ which are related to one another and to the motor
    outputs and sensory inputs by the transition probabilities given in such-and-such a
    Machine Table. The Machine Table mentioned in the Description will then be called the
    Functional Organization of 5 relative to that Description, and the 5, such that 5 is in
    state 5, at a given time will be called the Total State of 5 (at the time) relative to
    that Description. It should be noted that knowing the Total State of a system relative to
    a Description involves knowing a good deal about how the system is likely to ‘ behave


    ,

    given various combinations of sensory inputs, but does not involve knowing the physical
    realization of the 5, as, e.g., physical-chemical states of the brain. The 5″ to repeat,

    are specified only implicitly by the Description- i.e., specified only by the set of transition
    probabilities given in the Machine Table.

    The hypothesis that ‘ being in pain is a functional state of the organism

    may now be

    spelled out more exactly as follows:

    1. All organisms capable of feeling pain are Probabilistic Automata.
    2. Every organism capable of feeling pain possess es at least one Description of a
    certain kind (i.e., being capable of feeling pain is possessing an appropriate kind
    of Functional Organization).
    3. No organism capable of feeling pain possess es a decomposition into parts
    which separately possess Descriptions of the kind referred to in 2.
    4. For every Description of the kind referred to in 2, there exists a subset of the
    sensory inputs such that an organism with that Description is in pain when and
    only when some of its sensory inputs are in that subset.

    This hypothesis is admittedly vague, though surely no vaguer than the brain-state

    hypothesis in its present form. For example, one would like to know more about the
    kind of Functional Organization that an organism must have to be capable of feeling
    pain, and more about the marks that distinguish the subset of the sensory inputs
    referred to in 4. With respect to the first question, one can probably say that the
    Functional Organization must include something that resembles a


    preference function


    ,

    or at least a preference partial ordering and something that resembles an
    ‘inductive

    logic

    (i.e., the Machine must be able to ‘learn from experience

    ). In addition, it seems

    natural to require that the Machine possess

    pain sensors


    , i.e., sensory organs which

    normally signal damage to the Machine
    ‘s body, or dangerous temperatures, pressures,

    etc., which transmit a special subset of the inputs, the subset referred to in 4. Finally, and
    with respect to the second question, we would want to require at least that the inputs in
    the distinguished subset have a high disvalue on the Machine

    ‘s preference function or
    ordering (further conditions are discussed in the previous chapter). The purpose of
    condition 3 is to rule out such ‘organisms


    (if they can count as such) as swarms of bees

    as single pain-feelers. The condition 1 is, obviously, redundant, and is only introduced
    for expository reasons. (It is, in fact, empty, since everything is a Probabilistic Automaton

    under some Description.)
    I contend, in passing, that this hypothesis, in spite of its admitted vagueness, is far

    less vague than the

    physical-chemical state


    hypothesis is today, and far more susceptible

    to investigation of both a mathematical and an empirical kind. Indeed, to investigate
    this hypothesis is just to attempt to produce

    ‘mechanical’ models of organisms- and
    isn’t this, in a sense, just what psychology is about? The difficult step, of course, will be
    to pass from models of specific organisms to a nomull fonn for the psychological description

    of organisms- for this is what is required to make 2 and 4 precise. But this too
    seems to be an inevitable part of the program of psychology.

    I shall now compare the hypothesis just advanced with (a) the hypothesis that pain is
    a brain state, and (b) the hypothesis that pain is a behavior disposition.

    Functional State versus Brain State

    It may, perhaps, be asked if I am not somewhat unfair in taking the brain-state theorist
    to be talking about physical-chemical states of the brain. But (a) these are the only sorts
    of states ever mentioned by brain-state theorists. (b) The brain-state theorist usually
    mentions (with a certain pride, slightly reminiscent of the Village Atheist) the incompatibility

    of his hypothesis with all forms of dualism and mentalism. This is natural if

    physical-chemical states of the brain are what is at issue. However, functional states of
    whole systems are something quite different. In particular, the functional-state hypothesis
    is not incompatible with dualism! Although it goes without saying that the hypothesis
    is ‘mechanistic’ in its inspiration, it is a slightly remarkable fact that a system consisting
    of a body and a

    ‘soul’, if such things there be, can perfectly well be a Probabilistic
    Automaton. (c) One argument advanced by Smart is that the brain-state theory assumes
    only


    physical


    properties, and Smart finds

    ‘non-physical

    properties unintelligible. The

    Total States and the

    inputs

    ‘ defined above are, of course, neither mental nor physical
    per se, and I cannot imagine a functionalist advancing this argumentd ) If the brain-state
    theorist does mean (or at least allow) states other than physical- chemical states, then his
    hypothesis is completely empty, at least until he specifies what sort of

    ‘states’ he does
    mean.

    Taking the brain-state hypothesis in this way, then, what reasons are there to prefer
    the functional-state hypothesis over the brain-state hypothesis? Consider what the

    The Nature of Mental States 55

    S6 Hilary Putnam

    brain-state theorist has to do to make good his claims. He has to spedfy aphysical-
    chemical state such that any organism (not just a mammal) is in pain if and only if (a) it
    possess es a brain of a suitable physical- chemical structure; and (b) its brain is in that
    physical- chemical state. This means that the physical- chemical state in question must be
    a possible state of a mammalian brain, a reptilian brain, a mollusc

    ‘s brain (octopus es are
    mollusca. and certainly feel pain), etc. At the same time, it must not be a possible
    (physically possible) state of the brain of any physically possible creature that cannot
    feel pain. Even if such a state can be found, it must be nomologically certain that it will
    also be a state of the brain of any extraterrestrial life that may be found that will
    be capable of feeling pain before we can even entertain the supposition that it may be
    pain.

    It is not altogether impossible that such a state will be found. Even though octopus
    and mammal are examples of parallel (rather than sequential) evolution, for example,
    virtually identical structures (physically speaking) have evolved in the eye of the octopus

    and in the eye of the mammal, notwithstanding the fact that this organ has evolved
    from different kinds of cells in the two cases. Thus it is at least possible that parallel
    evolution, all over the universe, might always lead to one and the same physical

    ‘ corre-
    late’ of pain. But this is certainly an ambitious hypothesis.

    Finally, the hypothesis becomes still more ambitious when we realize that the brain-
    state theorist is not just saying that pain is a brain state; he is, of course, concerned to
    maintain that every psychological state is a brain state. Thus if we can find even one
    psychological predicate which can clearly be applied to both a mammal and an octopus
    (say ‘ hungry


    ), but whose physical- chemical

    ‘correlate’ is different in the two cases,
    the brain-state theory has collapsed. It seems to me overwhelmingly probable that we
    can do this. Granted, in such a case the brain-state theorist can save himself by ad
    hoc assumptions (e.g., defining the disjunction of two states to be a single


    physical-

    chemical state’), but this does not have to be taken seriously.
    Turning now to the considerations for the functional-state theory, let us begin with

    the fact that we identify organisms as in pain, or hungry, or angry, or in heat, etc., on
    the basis of their behavior. But it is a truism that similarities in the behavior of two
    systems are at least a reason to suspect similarities in the functional organization of the
    two systems, and a much Wtllker reason to suspect similarities in the actual physical
    details. Moreover, we


    expect the various psychological states- at least the basic ones,

    such as hunger, thirst, aggression, etc.- to have more or less similar
    ‘transition prob-

    abilities’ (within wide and i Il- defined limits, to be sure) with each other and with behavior
    in the case of different species, because this is an artifact of the way in which we

    identify these states. Thus, we would not count an animal as thirsty if its
    ‘unsatiated’

    behavior did not seem to be directed toward drinking and was not followed by
    , satiation

    for liquid
    ‘. Thus any animal that we count as capable of these various states will at

    least seem to have a certain rough kind of functional organization. And, as already
    remarked, if the program of finding psychological laws that are not species-specific-
    i.e., of finding a normal form for psychological theories of different species- ever
    succeeds, then it will bring in its wake a delineation of the kind of functional organization

    that is necessary and sufficient for a given psychological state, as well as a precise
    definition of the notion ‘psychological state

    ‘. In contrast, the brain-state theorist has to
    hope for the eventual development of neurophysiological laws that are species-independent

    , which seems much less reasonable than the hope that psychological laws (of a
    sufficiently general kind) may be species-independent, or, still weaker, that aspecies-

    independent fonn can be found in which psychological laws can be written .

    Functional State versus Behavior-Disposition

    The theory that being in pain is neither a brain state nor a functional state but a

    behavior disposition has one apparent advantage : it appears to agree with the way in

    which we verify that organisms are in pain . We do not in practice know anything about
    the brain state of an animal when we say that it is in pain; and we possess little if any

    knowledge of its functional organization , except in a crude intuitive way . In fact,
    however , this


    advantage


    is no advantage at all : for , although statements about how we

    verify that .r is A may have a good deal to do with what the concept of being A comes
    to , they have precious little to do with what the property A is. To argue on the ground
    just mentioned that pain is neither a brain state nor a functional state is like arguing
    that heat is not mean molecular kinetic energy &om the fact that ordinary people do not

    (they think ) ascertain the mean molecular kinetic energy of something when they verify
    that it is hot or cold . It is not necessary that they should ; what is necessary is that the
    marks that they take as indications of heat should in fact be explained by the mean
    molecular kinetic energy . And , similarly , it is necessary to our hypothesis that the marks
    that are taken as behavioral indications of pain should be explained by the fact that the

    organism is a functional state of the appropriate kind , but not that speakers should
    know that this is so.

    The difficulties with ‘ behavior disposition

    accounts are so well known that I shall
    do little more than recall them here. The difficulty

    – it appears to be more than a’
    difficulty ,


    in fact- of specifying the required behavior disposition except as


    the disposition

    of X to behave as if X were in pain

    , is the chief one, of course. In contrast , we

    can specify the functional state with which we propose to identify pain, at least roughly ,
    without using the notion of pain . Namely , the functional state we have in mind is the
    state of receiving sensory inputs which playa certain role in the Functional Organization

    of the organism . This role is characterized, at least partially , by the fact that the
    sense organs responsible for the inputs in question are organs whose function is to
    detect damage to the body , or dangerous extremes of temperature , pressure, etc., and

    by the fact that the

    inputs


    themselves, whatever their physical realization , represent a

    condition that the organism assigns a high disvalue to . As I stressed in ‘ The mental life
    of some machines


    , this does not mean that the Machine will always avoid being in the

    condition in question (

    pain


    ); it only means that the condition will be avoided unless

    not avoiding it is necessary to the attainment of some more highly valued goal . Since
    the behavior of the Machine (in this case, an organism ) will depend not merely on the

    sensory inputs , but also on the Total State (i.e., on other values, beliefs, etc.), it seems

    hopeless to make any general statement about how an organism in such a condition
    must behave; but this does not mean that we must abandon hope of characterizing the
    condition . Indeed, we have just characterized it .

    Not only does the behavior – disposition theory seem hopelessly vague; if the ‘ behav-

    ior’ referred to is peripheral behavior , and the relevant stimuli are peripheral stimuli
    (e.g ., we do not say anything about what the organism will do if its brain is operated
    upon ), then the theory seems clearly false. For example, two animals with all motor
    nerves cut will have the same actual and potential ‘ behavior’ (namely , none to speak
    of); but if one has cut pain Bbers and the other has uncut pain Bbers, then one will
    feel pain and the other won


    t . Again , if one person has cut pain Bbers, and another

    suppress es all pain responses deliberately due to some strong compulsion , then the
    actual and potential peripheral behavior may be the same, but one will feel pain and the
    other won


    t . (Some philosophers maintain that this last case is conceptually impossible ,

    but the only evidence for this appears to be that they can

    t, or don


    t want to , conceive of

    it .) If , instead of pain, we take some sensation the ‘ bodily expression

    of which is easier

    The Nature of Mental States 57

    58 Hilary Putnam

    Methodological Considerations

    So far we have considered only what might be called the

    empirical


    reasons for saying

    that being in pain is a functional state , rather than a brain state or a behavior disposition ;

    namely , that it seems more likely that the functional state we described is invariantly


    correlated


    with pain , species


    independently , than that there is either a physical

    -chemical
    state of the brain (must an organism have a brain to feel pain ? perhaps some ganglia

    will do ) or a behavior disposition so correlated . If this is correct , then it follows that the
    identification we proposed is at least a candidate for consideration . What of method –

    ological considerations ?

    The methodological considerations are roughly similar in all cases of reduction , so no

    surprises need be expected here . First , identification of psychological states with functional
    states means that the laws of psychology can be derived from statements of the

    form

    such -and -such organisms have such

    -and -such Descriptions

    together with the
    identification statements (‘ being in pain is such

    -and -such a functional state

    , etc .). Secondly

    , the presence of the functional state (i .e., of inputs which play the role we have
    described in the Functional Organization of the organism ) is not merely


    correlated

    with

    but actually explains the pain behavior on the part of the organism . Thirdly , the
    identification serves to exclude questions which (if a naturalistic view is correct ) represent

    an altogether wrong way of looking at the matter , e.g ., What is pain if it isn

    t

    either the brain state or the functional stater and What causes the pain to be always

    accompanied by this sort of functional stater In short , the identification is to be tentatively

    accepted as a

    theory which leads to both fruitful predictions and to fruitful

    questions, and which serves to discourage fruitless and empirically senseless questions ,
    where by


    empirically senseless


    I mean


    senseless


    not merely from the standpoint of

    verification , but from the standpoint of what there in fact is.

    Notes

    1. In this paper I wish to avoid the vexed question of the relation between pRins and pRin states. I only
    remark in passing that one common argument against identification of these two – namely, that a pain
    can be in one


    s ann but a state (of the organism) cannot be in one

    ‘s ann- is easily seen to be fallacious.
    2. There are some well-known remarks by Alonzo Church on this topic. Those remarks do not bear (as

    might at Ant be supposed) on the identification of concepts with synonymy-classes as such, but rather
    support the view that (in formal semantics) it is necessary to retain Frege

    ‘s distinction between the
    normal and the ‘oblique


    use of expressions. That is, even if we say that the concept of temperature is the

    synonymy-class of the word

    temperature


    , we must not thereby be led into the error of supposing that’the concept of temperature


    is synonymous with

    ‘the synonymy -class of the word

    temperature

    ” ‘ – for
    then ‘the concept of temperature

    ‘ and ‘ dtr Btgriff dtr T emperatur’ would not be synonymous, which they
    are. Rather, we must say that the concept of


    temperature


    rt/trs to the synonymy-class of the word’

    temperature

    (on this particular reconstruction); but that class is identifitd not as


    the synonymy-class to

    which such-and-such a word belongs

    , but in another way (e.g., as the synonymy-class whose membeR

    have such-and-such a characteristic use).

    • chpt10

    Calculate your order
    Pages (275 words)
    Standard price: $0.00
    Client Reviews
    4.9
    Sitejabber
    4.6
    Trustpilot
    4.8
    Our Guarantees
    100% Confidentiality
    Information about customers is confidential and never disclosed to third parties.
    Original Writing
    We complete all papers from scratch. You can get a plagiarism report.
    Timely Delivery
    No missed deadlines – 97% of assignments are completed in time.
    Money Back
    If you're confident that a writer didn't follow your order details, ask for a refund.

    Calculate the price of your order

    You will get a personal manager and a discount.
    We'll send you the first draft for approval by at
    Total price:
    $0.00
    Power up Your Academic Success with the
    Team of Professionals. We’ve Got Your Back.
    Power up Your Study Success with Experts We’ve Got Your Back.

    Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code ESSAYHELP