Phi unit 9

  Answer the following questions: Fallacy: 

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

• Name the fallacy that you were able to identify 

• Define the fallacy -based on the lectures and reading 

• Explain why you think it’s committed. Inductive Inference:

• Identify one inductive inference pattern that it uses 

Save Time On Research and Writing
Hire a Pro to Write You a 100% Plagiarism-Free Paper.
Get My Paper

• Reconstruct its premise(s) and conclusion Your Opinion and Your Reasons: 

• Do you think that drugs should be legalized, or perhaps that only certain drugs should be legalized? What are your reasons? 

1

  • The drug laws don’t work
  • Written by: Michael Huemer | Appears in: Issue 41
    July 20, 2009

    Let me begin with a story, and see what you think about it. A man named Flip owned a computer.
    Flip, however, took very bad care of his computer. He often ate and drank over the computer,
    which resulted in his spilling Coke on the keyboard on three occasions, ruining the keyboard each
    time. He installed software that slowed the machine’s performance and caused the operating
    system to become unstable. Flip thought these programs were “cool”, but most industry experts
    considered them shoddy products whose drawbacks far outweighed their usefulness. Finally,
    three weeks ago, Flip got angry at his computer and threw it on the floor. The motherboard and
    several other components were fatally damaged, so that Flip no longer has a working computer.
    End of story.

    Flip was an imprudent and irresponsible computer owner. He made several bad decisions. It
    would clearly have been better had he taken care of his computer, not installed harmful software,
    and never thrown it on the floor. This would have been better for the computer, for Flip, and even
    for society, for Flip would have been a more productive citizen with a working computer. So a
    question naturally arises: how might we prevent people from behaving like Flip?

    A solution fairly thrusts itself on our imagination (or at any rate, on the imagination of those who
    take their cue from modern politics): we could send the police after Flip, to drag him off and
    throw him in jail. That would send a message to other would-be computer abusers.

    What are we to think of this plan? Of course, as things stand, Flip will not be sent to prison
    because he has violated no law. But that just invites the question: Should Flip’s behaviour be
    against the law? It is clear enough that the behaviour was foolish and without redeeming social
    value. So why isn’t it illegal?

    Here is why: because what Flip did, he did to his own computer. If Flip had destroyed someone
    else’s computer, say a computer in a public library, then he would be held accountable by the
    state, and rightly so. Likewise, if he had destroyed his computer in a manner directly harmful to
    someone else—say, by throwing the computer at another person—then he would deserve to be
    punished. But he does not deserve to be punished purely for what he does, privately, with his own
    property.

    It isn’t that what Flip did was not sufficiently harmful. Flip could have had a top-of-the-line,
    $5,000 computer worth three months’ of his salary. It could have contained the only copies of his
    personal correspondence over the last twenty years, plus the Ph.D. dissertation he was working on
    for the last five years. None of that matters to assessing his legal liability. Nor is the point that no
    one else was made worse off by Flip’s behavior. Suppose that scholarship in his field of study

    2

    will be set back thirty years by the tragic loss of Flip’s brilliant dissertation. Furthermore, Flip
    will be unhappy for the next several months because of the loss of his computer, causing his
    family and friends also to be unhappy. Again, none of this matters to assessing Flip’s fitness for
    public sanctions. As long as what Flip destroyed is clearly understood to have been entirely his
    own property, and as long as he did not in the process take or damage anything that another
    person had a right to, his deplorable behaviour would not and should not be legally punished.
    Almost no one would favor changing the laws in that regard.

    This is our conception of property. When you own something, you may do with it as you wish,
    even including damaging or destroying it, up until the point at which you violate another person’s
    rights over what is theirs. This is what we generally accept when it comes to our material
    possessions—our computers, our clothes, our cars, and so on.

    Now, what about our bodies? Shouldn’t we have at least as much right to control our own bodies
    as we have to control a computer? For what is more authentically yours than your own body?

    Somehow, the majority of people disagree. Consider the case of Trip. Trip has a body. But like
    many of us, Trip takes rather poor care of this body. He often puts substances into it that damage
    his health and have little or no nutritional value. He claims that these substances give him great
    enjoyment, but most medical experts consider the harms to far outweigh any benefits of these
    substances. By ingesting them, Trip greatly reduces his overall life expectancy.

    What can be done about Trip? Whereas nearly everyone is content to leave Flip alone to make his
    own mistakes with computers, most individuals and governments would see Trip hauled away
    and forcibly confined for years, in punishment for his indiscretions. At least, they would if Trip’s
    preferred “substances” include marijuana, cocaine, heroin, or any of several other specific
    substances named in the law. We would not, however, see Trip punished if his preferred
    substances include only alcohol, tobacco, and fatty foods. Although more people are killed every
    year by the latter substances than by illegal drugs—over twenty times more in the case of
    tobacco—most would consider legal sanctions for smoking, alcohol consumption, and overeating
    to be taking things too far.

    Why this contrast in our attitudes? Why is consumption of illegal drugs viewed so differently
    from consumption of other harmful substances, or participation in self-harming activities more
    generally? One reason is the value of purity. Psychologist Jonathan Haidt has identified five
    broad kinds of ideas that influence people’s moral attitudes—ideas about harm, fairness, loyalty,
    authority, and purity. Conservatives tend to be more strongly influenced than liberals by the last
    three. In particular, many see illegal drugs as impure and as pollutants of the body. But few see
    alcohol, tobacco, or fatty foods in that way, even if they are objectively more harmful. This is
    partly because of social conditions created by the legal regime itself: we see normal, respected
    individuals drinking, smoking, and eating unhealthy foods in public all the time. We see no such
    thing for illegal drugs, which we tend to associate with sordid, poor, dangerous neighbourhoods
    and people.

    What we should realize, when we are influenced by these feelings, is that illegal drugs are not
    inherently unclean, any more than alcohol, tobacco, or canola oil. All of these are simply
    chemicals that people choose to ingest for enjoyment, and that can harm our health if used to
    excess. Most of the sordid associations we have with illegal drugs are actually the product of the
    drug laws: it is because of the laws that drugs are sold on the black market, that Latin American
    crime bosses are made rich, that government officials are corrupted, and that drug users rob

    3

    others to buy drugs. The drug laws create a regime in which crime burgeons: because legitimate
    businesses are prevented from providing the goods demanded by the market, criminals step in to
    provide the product, at greatly inflated prices. During America’s experiment with alcohol
    prohibition, organized crime grew bold and powerful from its booming trade in illegal alcohol.
    When prohibition ended, the alcohol business was taken over by legitimate businesses. Today,
    alcohol is sold in stores, not on the streets; it is shipped from breweries in the daylight, not
    smuggled across borders by criminal organizations; no government is corrupted by alcohol
    money; and virtually no one robs other people to get money to buy alcohol. The difference
    between the situation of alcohol and that of illegal drugs lies not in their chemical or
    pharmacological properties; it lies in the law. In the case of the drug trade, we have created laws
    that protect criminal organizations from noncriminal competition, thereby granting obscene
    profits to criminals.

    None of this is to deny that misuse and overuse of drugs create problems for the user and those
    around him. The same is true, as I have said, of alcohol, tobacco, and unhealthy foods. But
    without prohibition, the problems created by drug use would be mainly private problems; it is the
    law that enables the drug trade to damage and corrupt society.

    Most philosophers, in my experience, can be brought to agree with the case for legalisation. But
    there is another reason—apart from sentiments about purity—why most non-philosophers do not
    accept this case. That is that the legalization position strikes many as defeatist. We have a
    problem: drugs ruin many people’s lives. The legalisers’ position offers no solution to this
    problem, counselling instead that we merely learn to live with it. We hear this complaint often
    from the prohibitionists’ side. As conservative U.S. Senator Jon Kyl put it, “What [the
    legalisation advocates] all have in common is a defeatist mentality that America is losing the war
    on drugs, and a shared faith that we can somehow win it by surrendering.” The Senator’s last
    remark is of course a misstatement: legalisers do not propose to win the war on drugs by
    surrendering. They propose no way of winning at all. Those who advocated the repeal of alcohol
    prohibition likewise offered no way of winning the battle against drunkenness. Rather than trying
    to win that battle, we have learned to live with the enemy as best we can.

    Many conservatives feel repelled by this cynical approach. Those who feel this way would do
    well to learn from the views of their conservative colleagues about economic policy.
    Conservatives have long pointed up the unworkability of socialism. Many socialists find this
    critique cynical and defeatist: market economics offers no solution to the problems of human
    greed, poverty, and inequality. How can we be content to acquiesce in these problems, when
    another ideology offers a plan to perfect society and human nature?

    The key insight that these sentiments are missing is that expressed in Voltaire’s dictum, “The best
    is the enemy of the good.” Seeking the best imaginable result—seeking to eliminate a social
    problem—often leaves us worse off. That is because the best is almost always unattainable, and
    our pursuit of it interferes with more modest strategies that could have achieved a good result,
    reducing the problem’s size and its collateral effects. The insight conservatives bring to the
    discussion of at least some social issues is that human society is imperfect because
    human nature is imperfect. As long as there are human beings, there will be selfishness, there will
    be crime, there will be foolish choices and people who ruin their own and others’ lives. The root
    of the drug problem is not that there are too many drugs around, or that they are too cheap, or that
    people have yet to be sufficiently educated as to their harmful effects. The root of the problem
    lies in the fact that some human beings desire escape from their troubles, and that human beings
    are tempted more by immediate pleasures than by the long-term good. Until humans are replaced

    4

    by angels, that problem will not be solved, and to declare “war” on it is to declare war on human
    nature.

    This is not to justify complacency in the face of vice and suffering. The point is rather to reframe
    our task. Our goal should not be to solve problems or to win metaphorical wars. Our goal should
    be to mitigate problems. We should not ask “What will stop drug abuse in our society?” but
    “What will reduce the problems associated with drug use in the most cost-effective manner?”

    The war on drugs is not the answer to the latter question. Legalisation would reduce the social
    costs of the drug trade, for the reasons I have mentioned. It would greatly reduce crime and
    corruption, free up state resources, and restore respect for individual rights. Once we properly
    frame our task in confronting social problems, this will strike us, not as a defeatist appeal, but as
    the realistic and responsible approach.

    Michael Huemer is professor of philosophy at the University of Colorado at Boulder

      The drug laws don’t work

    PHIL110Critical Thinking – SPS CUNY

    Unit 9 Discussion Assignment
    Anything Wrong with this Argument?

    Step 1.

    Read an article that appeared in The Philosophers’ Magazine, entitled “The Drug Laws Don’t

    Work.” By Michael Huemer (see attached as a separate PDF).

    This article — “The Drug Laws Don’t Work” — was written by Michael Huemer, a philosophy

    professor at the University of Colorado. It first appeared in The Philosophers’ Magazine on July

    20, 2009. The article contains some very interesting inductive argumentative strategies,

    including analogy, causal argument, and enumerative induction. It also comes close to

    committing some fallacies such as weak analogy, false cause, and hasty generalization.

    Step 2.

    Once you’ve read the article, find an instance of where the argument comes dangerously close to

    committing a fallacy. Then find inductive inference pattern that this argument uses (such as

    inductive generalization (enumerative induction), statistical syllogism, analogy, or causal

    argument.

    Step 3.

    On the Discussion Forum, answer the following questions:

    Fallacy:

    • Name the fallacy that you were able to identify

    • Define the fallacy -based on the lectures and reading

    • Explain why you think it’s committed.

    Inductive Inference:

    • Identify one inductive inference pattern that it uses

    • Reconstruct its premise(s) and conclusion

    Your Opinion and Your Reasons:

    • Do you think that drugs should be legalized, or perhaps that only certain drugs should be

    legalized? What are your reasons?

    Step 4.

    Read and respond to other students’ posts with substantial comments that follow these

    commenting points:

    PHIL110 Critical Thinking – SPS CUNY

    • Do you think their reconstruction of the fallacy is well done? Does their explanation make

    sense? If not, what additional comments can you offer to clarify it.

    • Do you agree with the reasons they offer to answer the question about ‘legalizing

    drugs’? Which of their reasons do you disagree with and why?

    • Search the internet for a recent commentary (news article published within the last 3 years)

    about drug laws, legalization, punishments etc – and offer this article as a gift to your fellow

    student. Link to the article, then tell them why you are offering this article and how it related

    to their position (it might be supporting their view or contradicting it).

    • (NOTE: You can offer the same article to several students’ posts that you make comments

    on, as long as you connect the article specifically to their arguments on drug laws).

    Recommendations for Success and Grading Criteria:

    • Respond to the assignment with clear and detailed answers, organized thoughts.

    • Follow all assignment prompts and answers all prompt questions.

    • Incorporate relevant examples and evidence to support claims.

    • Write clearly and without errors a well-composed answer and post it on time.

    • Respond to other students with interesting comments and follow-up
    questions. Acknowledge all students who commented on your post.

    Calculate your order
    Pages (275 words)
    Standard price: $0.00
    Client Reviews
    4.9
    Sitejabber
    4.6
    Trustpilot
    4.8
    Our Guarantees
    100% Confidentiality
    Information about customers is confidential and never disclosed to third parties.
    Original Writing
    We complete all papers from scratch. You can get a plagiarism report.
    Timely Delivery
    No missed deadlines – 97% of assignments are completed in time.
    Money Back
    If you're confident that a writer didn't follow your order details, ask for a refund.

    Calculate the price of your order

    You will get a personal manager and a discount.
    We'll send you the first draft for approval by at
    Total price:
    $0.00
    Power up Your Academic Success with the
    Team of Professionals. We’ve Got Your Back.
    Power up Your Study Success with Experts We’ve Got Your Back.

    Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code ESSAYHELP